Portfolio Selection STÖR ® Harry Markowitz The Journal of Finance, Vol. 7, No. 1 (Mar., 1952), 77-91. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28195203%297%3Al%3C77%3APS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-l The Journal of Finance is currently published by American Finance Association. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/afina.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to creating and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.j stor.org/ Tue Jan 31 04:09:36 2006 PORTFOLIO SELECTION* Harry Markowitz The Rand Corporation The process of selecting a portfolio may be divided into two stages. The first stage starts with observation and experience and ends with beliefs about the future performances of available securities. The second stage starts with the relevant beliefs about future performances and ends with the choice of portfolio. This paper is concerned with the second stage. We first consider the rule that the investor does (or should) maximize discounted expected, or anticipated, returns. This rule is rejected both as a hypothesis to explain, and as a maximum to guide investment behavior. We next consider the rule that the investor does (or should) consider expected return a desirable thing and variance of return an undesirable thing. This rule has many sound points, both as a maxim for, and hypothesis about, investment behavior. We illustrate geometrically relations between beliefs and choice of portfolio according to the "expected returns—variance of returns" rule. One type of rule concerning choice of portfolio is that the investor does (or should) maximize the discounted (or capitalized) value of future returns.1 Since the future is not known with certainty, it must be "expected" or "anticipated" returns which we discount. Variations of this type of rule can be suggested. Following Hicks, we could let "anticipated" returns include an allowance for risk.2 Or, we could let the rate at which we capitalize the returns from particular securities vary with risk. The hypothesis (or maxim) that the investor does (or should) maximize discounted return must be rejected. If we ignore market imperfections the foregoing rule never implies that there is a diversified portfolio which is preferable to all non-diversified portfolios. Diversification is both observed and sensible; a rule of behavior which does not imply the superiority of diversification must be rejected both as a hypothesis and as a maxim. * This paper is based on work done by the author while at the Cowles Commission for Research in Economics and with the financial assistance of the Social Science Research Council. It will be reprinted as Cowles Commission Paper, New Series, No. 60. 1. See, for example, J. B. Williams, The Theory of Investment Value (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1938), pp. 55-75. 2. J. R. Hicks, Value and Capital (New York: Oxford University Press, 1939), p. 126. Hicks applies the rule to a firm rather than a portfolio. 77 78 The Journal oj Finance The foregoing rule fails to imply diversification no matter how the anticipated returns are formed; whether the same or different discount rates are used for different securities; no matter how these discount rates are decided upon or how they vary over time.3 The hypothesis implies that the investor places all his funds in the security with the greatest discounted value. If two or more securities have the same value, then any of these or any combination of these is as good as any other. We can see this analytically: suppose there are N securities; let rit be the anticipated return (however decided upon) at time / per dollar invested in security i; let dit be the rate at which the return on the ith security at time t is discounted back to the present; let Xi be the relative amount invested in security i. We exclude short sales, thus Xi ž 0 for all i. Then the discounted anticipated return of the portfolio is N / °° \ -2*«(2>'«) 00 Ri = 2^ dit rit is the discounted return of the ith security, therefore R = 2XiRi where Ri is independent of Xi. Since Xi ž 0 for all i and XXi = 1, R is a weighted average of Ri with the Xi as non-negative weights. To maximize R, we let Xi = 1 for i with maximum Ri. If several Raa, a = 1,. . ., K are maximum then any allocation with maximizes R. In no case is a diversified portfolio preferred to all non-diversified portfolios.4 It will be convenient at this point to consider a static model. Instead of speaking of the time series of returns from the ith security (f a, 7*2, . • ., rih . . .) we will speak of "the flow of returns" (r%) from the ith security. The flow of returns from the portfolio as a whole is 3. The results depend on the assumption that the anticipated returns and discount rates are independent of the particular investor's portfolio. 4. If short sales were allowed, an infinite amount of money would be placed in the security with highest r. Portfolio Selection 79 R = 2-X>i. As in the dynamic case if the investor wished to maximize "anticipated" return from the portfolio he would place all his funds in that security with maximum anticipated returns. There is a rule which implies both that the investor should diversify and that he should maximize expected return. The rule states that the investor does (or should) diversify his funds among all those securities which give maximum expected return. The law of large numbers will insure that the actual yield of the portfolio will be almost the same as the expected yield.5 This rule is a special case of the expected returns— variance of returns rule (to be presented below). It assumes that there is a portfolio which gives both maximum expected return and minimum variance, and it commends this portfolio to the investor. This presumption, that the law of large numbers applies to a portfolio of securities, cannot be accepted. The returns from securities are too intercorrelated. Diversification cannot eliminate all variance. The portfolio with maximum expected return is not necessarily the one with minimum variance. There is a rate at which the investor can gain expected return by taking on variance, or reduce variance by giving up expected return. We saw that the expected returns or anticipated returns rule is inadequate. Let us now consider the expected returns—variance of returns (E-V) rule. It will be necessary to first present a few elementary concepts and results of mathematical statistics. We will then show some implications of the E-V rule. After this we will discuss its plausibility. In our presentation we try to avoid complicated mathematical statements and proofs. As a consequence a price is paid in terms of rigor and generality. The chief limitations from this source are (1) we do not derive our results analytically for the «-security case; instead, we present them geometrically for the 3 and 4 security cases; (2) we assume static probability beliefs. In a general presentation we must recognize that the probability distribution of yields of the various securities is a function of time. The writer intends to present, in the future, the general, mathematical treatment which removes these limitations. We will need the following elementary concepts and results of mathematical statistics: Let F be a random variable, i.e., a variable whose value is decided by chance. Suppose, for simplicity of exposition, that F can take on a finite number of values yh y2, '."". . , yar- Let the probability that F = 5. Williams, op. cit., pp. 68, 69. 8o The Journal oj Finance yi, be pi; that Y = y2 be fr etc. The expected value (or mean) of Y is defined to be E = piyi + p2y2 +-----+ pNyN The variance of Y is defined to be V = pi (yx -E)2 + p2 (y2 -E)2 +. , . + pN (yN -E)2. F is the average squared deviation of Y from its expected value. F is a commonly used measure of dispersion. Other measures of dispersion, closely related to F are the standard deviation, E and V < V. Consider all points with a given expected return E; i.e., all points on the isomean line associated with E. The point of the isomean line at which V takes on its least value is the point at which the isomean line 9. The isomean "curves" are as described above except when mi — M2 = M3- In the latter case all portfolios have the same expected return and the investor chooses the one with minimum variance. As to the assumptions implicit in our description of the isovariance curves see footnote 12. Portfolio Selection 85 is tangent to an isovariance curve. We call this point X(E). If we let E vary, X(E) traces out a curve. Algebraic considerations (which we omit here) show us that this curve is a straight line. We will call it the critical line /. The critical line passes through X for this point minimizes V for all points with E(Xi, X2) = E. As we go along I in either direction from X, V increases. The segment of the critical line from X to the point where the critical Ľne crosses X \ ^ Direďion of \ ^y\ increasing E* WW \ X *direction of increasing E depends on fxu fi>. ft3 Fig. 2 the boundary of the attainable set is part of the efficient set. The rest of the efficient set is (in the case illustrated) the segment of the ab line from d tob. b is the point of maximum attainable E. In Figure 3, X lies outside the admissible area but the critical line cuts the admissible area. The efficient line begins at the attainable point with minimum variance (in this case on the ab line). It moves toward b until it intersects the critical line, moves along the critical line until it intersects a boundary and finally moves along the boundary to b. The reader may increasing E Fig. 3 efficient portfolios« Fig. 4 Portfolio Selection 87 wish to construct and examine the following other cases: (1) X lies outside the attainable set and the critical line does not cut the attainable set. In this case there is a security which does not enter into any efficient portfolio. (2) Two securities have the same /*,-. In this case the isomean lines are parallel to a boundary line. It may happen that the efficient portfolio with maximum £ is a diversified portfolio. (3) A case wherein only one portfolio is efficient. The efficient set in the 4 security case is, as in the 3 security and also the N security case, a series of connected line segments. At one end of the efficient set is the point of minimum variance; at the other end is a point of maximum expected return10 (see Fig. 4). Now that we have seen the nature of the set of efficient portfolios, it is not difficult to see the nature of the set of efficient (£, V) combinations. In the three security case E = a0 + «A + (hX2 is a plane; V = b0 + biXi + hX2 + W1I2 + &ii^j + #22^2 *s a Paraboloid.u As shown in Figure 5, the section of the E-plane over the efficient portfolio set is a series of connected line segments. The section of the F-parab-oloid over the efficient portfolio set is a series of connected parabola segments. If we plotted V against E for efficient portfolios we would again get a series of connected parabola segments (see Fig. 6). This result obtains for any number of securities. Various reasons recommend the use of the expected return-variance of return rule, both as a hypothesis to explain well-established investment behavior and as a maxim to guide one's own action. The rule serves better, we will see, as an explanation of, and guide to, ''investment" as distinguished from "speculative" behavior. 4 10. Just as we used the equation y] X» = 1 to reduce the dimensionality in the three security case, we can use it to represent the four security case in 3 dimensional space. Eliminating X< we get E = E(Xh X2, Xz), V = V(Xh X2} Xz). The attainable set is represented, in three-space, by the tetrahedron with vertices (0,0,0), (0,0,1), (0,1,0), (1,0,0), representing portfolios with, respectively, X4 = 1, Xz = 1, X2 = 1, X\ = 1. Let im be the subspace consisting of all points with Xi = 0. Similarly we can define Sau . . . , oo to be the subspace consisting of all points with Xi = 0, i j£ a\, . . . , aa. For each subspace sai, . . . , aa we can define a critical line laiy . . . aa. This line is the locus of points P where P minimizes V for all points in sai, . . . , aa with the same E as P. If a point is in sai, . . . , aa and is efficient it must be on lai, . . . , aa. The efficient set may be traced out by starting at the point of minimum available variance, moving continuously along various lai, . . . , aa according to definite rules, ending in a point which gives maximum E. As in the two dimensional case the point with minimum available variance may be in the interior of the available set or on one of its boundaries. Typically we proceed along a given critical line until either this line intersects one of a larger subspace or meets a boundary (and simultaneously the critical line of a lower dimensional subspace). In either of these cases the efficient line turns and continues along the new line. The efficient line terminates when a point with maximum E is reached. 11. See footnote 8. Fig. 5 set of efficient portfolios efficient E,V combinations \. Fig. 6 Portfolio Selection 89 Earlier we rejected the expected returns rule on the grounds that it never implied the superiority of diversification. The expected return-variance of return rule, on the other hand, implies diversification for a wide range of ju*, a^. This does not mean that the E-V rule never implies the superiority of an undiversified portfolio. It is conceivable that one security might have an extremely higher yield and lower variance than all other securities; so much so that one particular undiversified portfolio would give maximum E and minimum V. But for a large, presumably representative range of /x»-, 0, dU/dE < 0) he will never accept an actuarially fair14 bet. But if 13. If R is a random variable that takes on a finite number of values fi,. . ., rn with n probabilities pi,..., pn respectively, and expected value E, then M% =» / j piifi — E)3 i=l 14. One in which the amount gained by winning the bet times the probability of winning is equal to the amount lost by losing the bet, times the probability of losing. Portfolio Selection 91 U = U(E9 V, M z) and if dU/dMz 9* 0 then there are some fair bets which would be accepted. Perhaps—for a great variety of investing institutions which consider yield to be a good thing; risk, a bad thing; gambling, to be avoided—E, V efficiency is reasonable as a working hypothesis and a working maxim. Two uses of the E-V principle suggest themselves. We might use it in theoretical analyses or we might use it in the actual selection of portfolios. In theoretical analyses we might inquire, for example, about the various effects of a change in the beliefs generally held about a firm, or a general change in preference as to expected return versus variance of return, or a change in the supply of a security. In our analyses the Xi might represent individual securities or they might represent aggregates such as, say, bonds, stocks and real estate.15 To use the E-V rule in the selection of securities we must have procedures for finding reasonable pi and a\y. These procedures, I believe, should combine statistical techniques and the judgment of practical men. My feeling is that the statistical computations should be used to arrive at a tentative set of pi and Judgment should then be used in increasing or decreasing some of these pi and cr^- on the basis of factors or nuances not taken into account by the formal computations. Using this revised set of pi and a^ the set of efficient E, V combinations could be computed, the investor could select the combination he preferred, and the portfolio which gave rise to this E, V combination could be found. One suggestion as to tentative piy