IA169 System Verification and Assurance CTL Model Checking Jiří Barnat Liner vs. Branching Time Pnueli, 1977 System is viewed as a set of state sequences — Runs. System properties are given as properties of runs, ... and can be described with a linear-time logic. Clarke & Emerson, 1980 System is viewed as a branching structure of possible executions from individual system states — Computation Tree. System properties are given as properties of the tree, ... and can be described with a branching-time logic. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 2/34 System and Computation Tree 1 2 1 1 1 1 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 3/34 Section Computation Tree Logic (CTL) IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 4/34 CTL Informally Possible Future Computations For a given node of a computation tree, the sub-tree rooted in the given node describes all possible runs the system can still take. Every such a run is possible future computation. CTL Formulae Allow For Specification of state qualities with atomic propositions. Quantify over possible future computations. Restrict the set of possible future computations with (quantified) LTL operators. Example ϕ ≡ EF(a) It is possible to take a future computation such that a will hold true in the computation eventually. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 5/34 Syntax of CTL Let AP by a set of atomic propositions. If p ∈ AP, then p is a CTL formula. If ϕ is a CTL formula, then ¬ϕ is a CTL formula. If ϕ and ψ are CTL formulae, then ϕ ∨ ψ is a CTL formula. If ϕ is a CTL formula, then EX ϕ is a CTL formula. If ϕ and ψ are CTL formulae, then E[ϕ U ψ] is a CTL formula. If ϕ and ψ are CTL formulae, then A[ϕ U ψ] is a CTL formula. Alternatively (Backus-Naur Form) ϕ ::= p | ¬ϕ | ϕ ∨ ϕ | EX ϕ | E[ϕ U ϕ] | A[ϕ U ϕ] IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 6/34 Syntactic Shortcuts Already Known The standard shortcuts from the propositional logic. Syntactic shortcuts from LTL F ϕ ≡ true U ϕ G ϕ ≡ ¬F ¬ϕ Deduced CTL Operators EF ϕ ≡ E[true U ϕ] AF ϕ ≡ A[true U ϕ] EG ϕ ≡ ¬AF ¬ϕ AG ϕ ≡ ¬EF ¬ϕ AX ϕ ≡ ¬EX ¬ϕ IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 7/34 Models of CTL formulae Model of a CTL formula Let AP be a set of atomic propositions. Model of a CTL formula is a state s ∈ S of Kripke structure M = (S, T, I, s0). Reminder Run of a Kripke structure is maximal path starting at the initial state of the structure. Finite maximal paths are viewed as infinite runs due to infinite repetition of the last state on the path. Notation Let s ∈ S be a state of Kripke structure M = (S, T, I, s0). PM(s) = {π | π is a run initiated at state s} IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 8/34 Semantics of CTL Assumptions Let AP be a set of atomic propositions. Let p ∈ AP be an atomic proposition. Let s ∈ S be a state of Kripke structure M = (S, T, I, s0). Let ϕ, ψ denote syntactically correct CTL formulae. Semantics s |= p iff p ∈ I(s) s |= ¬ϕ iff ¬(s |= ϕ) s |= ϕ ∨ ψ iff s |= ϕ or s |= ψ s |= EX ϕ iff ∃π ∈ PM(s).π(1) |= ϕ s |= E[ϕ U ψ] iff ∃π ∈ PM(s).(∃k ≥ 0.(π(k) |= ψ and ∀0 ≤ i < k.π(i) |= ϕ)) s |= A[ϕ U ψ] iff ∀π ∈ PM(s).(∃k ≥ 0.(π(k) |= ψ and ∀0 ≤ i < k.π(i) |= ϕ)) IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 9/34 Task Atomic Propositions AP={a, b, Req, Ack, Restart} Express with CTL Formulae A state where a is true, but b is not, is reachable. Whenever system receives a request Req, it generates acknowledgement Ack eventually. In every run there are infinitely many b’s. There is always an option to reset the system (reach state Restart). IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 10/34 Section Model Checking CTL IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 11/34 Problem Statements Model Checking CTL Let M = (S, T, I, s0) be a Kripke structure. Let ϕ be a CTL formula. Does initial state of M satisfies ϕ? Alternatively Let M = (S, T, I, s0) be a Kripke structure. Let ϕ be a CTL formula. Compute a set of states of M satisfying ϕ. Above mentioned approaches are also referred to as to Local model checking problem — M, s0 |= ϕ. Global model checking problem — {s | M, s |= ϕ}. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 12/34 Algorithm for CTL Model Checking — Idea Observation If the validity of formulae ϕ and ψ is known for all states, it is easy to deduce validity of formulae ¬ϕ, ϕ ∨ ψ, EX ϕ, . . . . CTL Model Checking – Sketch Let M = (S, T, I) be a Kripke structure and ϕ a CTL Formula. A labelling function label : S → 22ϕ is computed such that it gives validity of all sub-formulae of ϕ for all states of Kripke structure M. Obviously, s0 |= ϕ ⇐⇒ ϕ ∈ label(s0). Function label is computed gradually for individual sub-formulae of ϕ, starting with the simplest sub-formula and proceeding towards more complex sub-formulae, ending with ϕ itself. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 13/34 Sub-formulae of a CTL Formula Sub-formulae of formula ϕ Let ϕ be a CTL formula. The set of all sub-formulae of formula ϕ is denoted by 2ϕ. 2ϕ is defined inductively according to the structure of ϕ. Inductive Definition of 2ϕ 1) ϕ ∈ 2ϕ (ϕ is a sub-formula of ϕ) 2) If η ∈ 2ϕ and η ≡ ¬ψ, then ψ ∈ 2ϕ η ≡ ψ1 ∨ ψ2, then ψ1, ψ2 ∈ 2ϕ η ≡ EX ψ, then ψ ∈ 2ϕ η ≡ E[ψ1 U ψ2], then ψ1, ψ2 ∈ 2ϕ η ≡ A[ψ1 U ψ2], then ψ1, ψ2 ∈ 2ϕ 3) Nothing else. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 14/34 Equivalent Existential Form of CTL Observation It is easier to prove validity of existential quantified modal operators than validity of universally quantified ones. For the purpose of verification of CTL-specified properties, it is possible to express the CTL formula in an equivalently expressive existential form of CTL. Equivalent CTL Syntax ϕ ::= p | ¬ϕ | ϕ ∨ ϕ | EX ϕ | E[ϕ U ϕ] | EG ϕ Task Express formula EG ϕ in the original syntax of CTL. Give accordingly modified definition of the set of sub-formulae of ϕ for the above mentioned equivalent syntax. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 15/34 Algorithm for CTL Model-Checking INPUT: Kripke structure M = (S, T, I, s0), CTL formula ϕ. OUTPUT: True, if s0 |= ϕ; False otherwise. proc CTLMC(ϕ, M) label := I Solved := AP ∩ 2ϕ while ϕ ∈ Solved do foreach ( η ∈ {¬ψ1, ψ1 ∨ ψ2, EX ψ1, E[ψ1 U ψ2], EG ψ1 | ψ1, ψ2 ∈ Solved})do if (η ∈ 2ϕ and η ∈ Solved) then label := updateLabel(η, label, M) Solved := Solved ∪ {η} fi od od return (ϕ ∈ label(s0)) end IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 16/34 Algorithm for CTL Model-Checking updateLabel() proc updateLabel(η, label, M) if (η ≡ E[ψ1 U ψ2]) then return checkEU(ψ1, ψ2, label, M) fi if (η ≡ EG ψ) then return checkEG(ψ, label, M) fi foreach ( s ∈ S)do if (η ≡ ¬ψ and ψ ∈ label(s)) or (η ≡ ψ1 ∨ ψ2 and (ψ1 ∈ label(s) ∨ ψ2 ∈ label(s))) or (η ≡ EX ψ and (∃t ∈ {t | (s, t) ∈ T} such that ψ ∈ label(t))) then label(s) := label(s) ∪ {η} fi od return label end IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 17/34 Algorithm for CTL Model-Checking E[ψ1 U ψ2] INPUT: Kripke structure M = (S, T, I), Labelling function label : S → 2ϕ , correct w.r.t validity of ψ1 and ψ2 OUTPUT: Labelling function label : S → 2ϕ , correct w.r.t E[ψ1 U ψ2] proc checkEU(ψ1, ψ2, label, M) Q := {s | ψ2 ∈ label(s)} foreach ( s ∈ Q)do label(s) := label(s) ∪ {E[ψ1 U ψ2]} od while (Q = ∅) do choose s ∈ Q Q := Q {s} foreach ( t ∈ {t | T(t, s)}) do /* all immediate predecessors */ if (E[ψ1 U ψ2] ∈ label(t) ∧ ψ1 ∈ label(t)) then label(t) := label(t) ∪ {E[ψ1 U ψ2]} Q := Q ∪ {t} fi od od return label end IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 18/34 Strongly Connected Components Sub-graph Let G = (V , E) be a graph, ie. E ⊆ V × V . Graph G = (V , E ) is called sub-graph of G if it holds that V ⊆ V and E = E ∩ V × V . Sub-graph C = (V , E ) of G = (V , E) is called Strongly Connected Component, if ∀u, v ∈ V it holds that (u, v) ∈ E ∗ and (v, u) ∈ E ∗. Maximal Strongly Connected Component (SCC), if C is strongly connected component and for every v ∈ (V V ) it is the case that (V ∪ {v}, E ∩ (V ∪ {v} × V ∪ {v})) is not. Non-trivial SCC, if C is Strongly Connected Component and E = ∅. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 19/34 Algorithm for CTL Model-Checking EG ψ INPUT: Kripke structure M = (S, T, I, s0), Labelling function label : S → 2ϕ , correct w.r.t. ψ OUTPUT: Labelling function label : S → 2ϕ , correct w.r.t. EG ψ proc checkEG(ψ, label, M) S’ := {s | ψ ∈ label(s)} SCC := {C | C is non-trivial SCC G = (S , T ∩ S × S )} Q := C∈SCC {s | s ∈ C} foreach ( s ∈ Q)do label(s) := label(s) ∪ {EG ψ} od while Q = ∅ do choose s ∈ Q Q := Q {s} foreach ( t ∈ (S ∩ {t | T(t, s)}))do /* all immediate predecessors in S */ if EG ψ ∈ label(t) then label(t) := label(t) ∪ {EG ψ} Q := Q ∪ {t} fi od od end IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 20/34 Complexity of Algorithm for CTL Model Checking Observation Every CTL formula ϕ is made of at most | ϕ | sub-formulae. Decomposition of every sub-graph of G = (S, T) into SCCs can be done in time O(| S | + | T |). Every call to updateLabel terminates in time O(| S | + | T |). Overall complexity Algorithm CTLMC exhibits O(| ϕ || S |) space and O(| ϕ | (| S | + | T |)) time complexity. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 21/34 Example: Microwave oven AG(Start =⇒ AF(Heat)) IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 22/34 Example: Microwave oven AG(Start =⇒ AF(Heat)) Transformation of formula ϕ ≡ AG(Start =⇒ AF(Heat)) AG(Start =⇒ AF(Heat)) AG(¬(Start ∧ ¬AF(Heat))) AG(¬(Start ∧ EG(¬Heat))) ¬EF(Start ∧ EG(¬Heat)) ¬E[true U (Start ∧ EG(¬Heat))] Validity of sub-formulae [S(ϕ) = {s | s |= ϕ}] S(Start) = {2, 5, 6, 7} S(Heat) = {4, 7} S(¬Heat) = {1, 2, 3, 5, 6} S(EG(¬Heat)) = {1, 2, 3, 5} S(Start ∧ EG(¬Heat)) = {2, 5} S(E[true U (Start ∧ EG(¬Heat))]) = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7} S(¬E[true U (Start ∧ EG(¬Heat))]) = ∅ IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 23/34 Section CTL∗ IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 24/34 CTL∗ as Extension of CTL Observation Every use of temporal operator in a formula of CTL must be immediately preceded with a quantifier, i.e. use of a modal operator without quantification is not possible. Logic CTL∗ Branching time logic. Similar to CTL. Unlike CTL, allows for standalone use of modal operators. Example A[p ∧ X(¬p)] is CTL∗, but is not CTL formula. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 25/34 Syntax of CTL∗ Types of CTL∗ formulae Quantifiers E and A are standalone operators in syntax construction rules. As a result there are two types of formulae in CTL: path and state formulae. Application of E and A operators on a path formula (formula of which model is a run of Kripke structure) results in a state formula (formula of which model is a state of Kripke structure) Syntax of CTL∗ state formula ϕ ::= p | ¬ϕ | ϕ ∨ ϕ | E ψ path formula ψ ::= ϕ | ¬ψ | ψ ∨ ψ | X ψ | ψ U ψ IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 26/34 Semantics of CTL∗ Assumption Let AP be a set of atomic propositions, and p ∈ AP. Let M = (S, T, I) be a Kripke structure. Let ϕi denote CTL∗ state formulae, and ψi denote CTL∗ state formulae. Semantics M, s |= p iff p ∈ I(s) M, s |= ¬ϕ1 iff ¬(M, s |= ϕ1) M, s |= ϕ1 ∨ ϕ2 iff M, s |= ϕ1 or M, s |= ϕ2 M, s |= E ψ1 iff ∃π ∈ PM (s).π |= ψ1 M, π |= ϕ1 iff M, π(0) |= ϕ1 M, π |= ¬ψ1 iff ¬(M, π |= ψ1) M, π |= ψ1 ∨ ψ2 iff M, π |= ψ1 or M, π |= ψ2 M, π |= X ψ1 iff M, π1 |= ψ1 M, π |= ψ1 U ψ2 iff ∃k ≥ 0.(M, πk |= ψ2 and ∀0 ≤ i < k.M, πi |= ψ1) IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 27/34 Section Comparison of Expressive Power of LTL, CTL and CTL∗ IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 28/34 Model Unification Observation Every LTL formula is a CTL∗ path formula. Every CTL formula is a CTL∗ state formula. Model of a path formula is a run of Kripke structure. Model of a state formula is a state of Kripke structure. Not very suitable for comparison. Model Unification For the purpose of comparison we define how a CTL∗ path formula is evaluated in a state of Kripke structure. Let ψ be CTL∗ path formula, then M, s |= ψ iff M, s |= A ψ IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 29/34 Motivation Goals We intend to find out whether there are properties (formulae) that can be expressed in one of the logic, but cannot be expressed in another one. We intend to find out in which logic more properties can be expressed. We intend to identify concrete properties, that cannot be expressed in some other logic, i.e. to find out a formula of logic L1, for which an equivalent formula of logic L2 does not exist. Formula Equivalence Formulae ϕ and ψ are equivalent if and only if for any possible Kripke structure M = (S, T, I, s0) and any state s ∈ S it is true that M, s |= ϕ iff M, s |= ψ. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 30/34 Equivalent Expressive Power Equivalently Expressive Temporal logic L1 and L2 have the same expressive power, if for all Kripke structures M = (S, T, I, s0) and states s ∈ S it holds that ∀ϕ ∈ L1.(∃ψ ∈ L2.(M, s |= ϕ ⇐⇒ M, s |= ψ)) (1) ∧ ∀ψ ∈ L2.(∃ϕ ∈ L1.(M, s |= ϕ ⇐⇒ M, s |= ψ)). (2) Less Expressiveness If only statement (1) is valid, then logic L1 is less expressive than logic L2, and vice versa. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 31/34 Comparison of LTL, CTL, and CTL∗ Theorem LTL and CTL are incomparable in expressive power. 1) AG(EF(q)) is a CTL formula that cannot be expressed in LTL. 2) FG(q) is an LTL formula that cannot be expressed in CTL. Example – Proof Sketch for 1) Find two different Kripke structures and identify two states that can be differentiated with CTL formula AG(EF(q)), but cannot be differentiated with any LTL formula (they generate the same set of runs). Example – Intuition behind 2) [proof is too complex] Show that CTL formula AF(AG(q)) is not equivalent to LTL formula FG(q). IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 32/34 Comparison of LTL, CTL, and CTL∗ Consequence CTL∗ is strictly more expressive than LTL. Every LTL formula is a CTL∗ formula. CTL∗ formula AG(EFq) is not expressible in LTL. Consequence 2 CTL∗ is strictly more expressive than CTL. Every CTL formula is a CTL∗ formula. CTL∗ formula FG(q) is not expressible in CTL. Observation There are properties expressible on both LTL and CTL. CTL formula A[p U q] is equivalent to LTL formula p U q. IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 33/34 Homework Homework Solve The wolf, goat and cabbage problem with NuSMV Moshe Vardi: Branching vs. Linear Time: Final Showdown IA169 System Verification and Assurance – 05 str. 34/34