'74 Bureaucracy as an Organizational System able to eliminate the usual power dependencies but must rely instead on a rigid and authoritarian system of hierarchical social relations. Such a system can survive only because of the very deep and anachronistic dichotomy between managers and managed and the acceptance, partial at least, of their inferior social position by the subordinates. It is reproducing, forty years later, the paradox and contradictions of scientific work organization. THE BUREAUCRATIC SYSTEM OF ORGANIZATION The Problem Study of the way power is allocated and an analysis of the bargaining strategies between individuals and groups within an organization are unusual starting points from which to try to reach an understanding of the function of an organization. We have taken this course because of its provocative and challenging properties in a domain that often seems paralyzed by formalism. Our effort appears to have been worth-while. For example, the distinction between organizations characterized by a stationary power equilibrium and organizations with constantly shifting systems of bargaining is apparently useful for the theory of organization. However, as we have also shown, the world of power is only one aspect of the complex relationship between the individual and the organization. The world of consensus and the world of the co-operative game are other important aspects of this basic relationship. We shall approach our subject in another, broader way. We shall attempt to analyze these two complementary aspects of the functioning of the organizations we have studied and we shall interpret our data in the light of the theoryof bureaucracy—that theory in terms of which sociologists since Max Weber have been considering the processes of organization. There is a paradox, however, in the long series of discussions over the theory of bureaucracy. During the last fifty years, many first-rate social scientists have thought of bureaucracy as one of the key ques- j tions of both modern sociology and modern political science. Max j Weber had furnished a very brilliant description of the "ideal type" ola bureaucratic organization, and a suggestive analysis of its historical development, that apparently paved the way^for a poskive yalue-free sociological analysis. Yet the discussion about bureaucracy is still, to a large extent, the domain of the myths and pathos of ideology. The paradox, indeed, exists already in Weber's work. In his studies on law and on Prussian bureaucracy, it is true, Weber presents a view which is richer and more sophisticated than the rationales iy6 Bureaucracy as an Organizational System ist model of the famous chapter of Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. But when he claims the superiority of modern bureaucracies that embody the "ideal type," one may wonder^ whether JiejJojsjMOlunkj^t these organizations succeed only inasmuch as thej^can impose^ ^hstanjJMjaid."^n8g^Siamount of .standardizatiQn pn'IEeir menv bers, Some of his statements show how much he was worried by such a trend.1 Among Weber's successors and contemporaries who used similar models more rigidly, contradictions are still deeper. On the one hand, most authors consider the bureaucratic organization to be the embodiment of rationality in the modern world, and, as such, to be .intrinsically superior to all other possible forms of organization. On j the other hand, many authors—often the same ones—consider it a I sort of Leviathan, preparing the enslavement of the human race. Optimism and pessimism are mixed in various ways. Whatever their proportions, there is always a double belief in the superiority of bureaucratic rationality—in the domain M.„cffipi§Bcy» and in its threateningjmp domain of human values. This was well exemplified by Robert Michels' syllogism of the "iron law." Michels, after cruelly "disenchanting" the "charismatic" enthusiasm of the Socialist movement, pointed to the dilemma of all ! democratic social action, reformist or revolutionary: democratic social : action is possibly and. bureau: i cratic organization is destructive or democratic values.2 This paradoxical view of bureaucracy in Western thought has paralyzed positive thinking on the problem and has favored the making of catastrophic prognostications. This has been most clearly perceptible in the great stream of revolutionary pessimism which has so pervaded Western political and social thought from Rosa Luxemburg and Trotsky to Bruno Rizzi, Simone Weil, and C. Wright Mills—to cite only the most famous names. A desperate gamble is the only hope. The picture is blackened, and the attack against what is felt to be inevitable if human beings accept their fate is exaggerated. Thus, by a pointing up of the paradox, only one alternative is left—the dialectical overstepping of revolutionary belief. The same paradox is also perceptible in more conservative circles. For example, it may be discerned in Burnham's simplifications, and in the great number of attacks, such as those of William H. Whyte, 1See, for example Max Weber's remarks at the 1909 convention o£ the Verein fur Sozialpolitik, as quoted by J. P. Mayer, Max Weher and German Politics (London: Faber & Faber, 1943), pp. 127-28; and by Reinhard Bendix, Max Weber: An Intellectual Portrait (New York: Doubleday, i960), pp. 455-56. % Robert Michels, Zur Soziologie des Partetwesens in der modernen Demokratie (Leipzig, 1912). The Bureaucratic System of Organization 177 Jr., against bigness and the bureaucratization of modern life. As Alvm Gouldner quite sensibly said: Wrapping themselves in the shrouds of nineteenth century political economy, some social scientists appear to be bent on resurrecting the dismal science. Instead of telling men how bureaucracy might be mitigated, they insist that it is inevitable.3 March and Simon have argued that Max Weber's thinking about bureaucracy corresponds to the early rationalist theory about numan behavior in organizations. This statement may be exaggerated as regards Weber himself,4 but it is quite accurate for Michels and all the revolutionary analysts of bureaucracy. We':go even farther and suggest that the modern "disjn^alsc leHuat"sophistication^ results, from its. relying on the .same crude theory" o£., KumaS motivation as the scientific engineers. It is only because its exponents accept, at their face value, the Taylorian arguments, that they can believe that modern organizations are succeed-j ing because of their evil features. ' The first decisive progress in resolving this contradiction was made when Robert K. Merton, and after him other American sociologists like Gouldner and Selznick, began to question the perfection of the "ideal type," ancTto chscuss, m aj^sjBwand"^^^KaI way, whether tne^pp^iBolTbetween organizational efficiency and the freedom of. th^ndividual was actually possible. Beginning with the theory of unintended con sequences successive research by the sociologists of bureaucracy has suggested that the routine and oppressive aspects of bureaucracy are so many elements of what may be described as a ....."viciouscircle" j* that develops from the resistance of the human factor to the mechanistic rationalist theory of behavior which is being imposed on it. This very resistance, paradoxically, tends to reinforce the use of the theory. Research.has demonstrated that the ideal type! of bureaucracy is far from Joeing cpmpl^ly^efficient. \ "Alvin Gouldner, "Metaphysical Pathos and the Theory of Bureaucracy," in Amitai Etzioni, Complex Organizations (New York: Holt, Rinehart, 1961), p. 82. 1 One can argue that Weber is more interested in the problem of social control than in the problem of rationality, and that he never forgets to take into account the fact that a bureaucracy must have some kind of legitimacy and thus rely ultimately ^n,,consensus^ Yet one can notice that, in his analysis of bureaucratic rationality, he emphasizes above all the predictability requirements and the standardization of behavior that provides the only way to meet them. There we can understand how his ideas can converge with those of promoters of scientific work-organization. If the latter do not want to see anything but the simplest economic motivations in human behavior, this is because such a simplified approach makes it possible for them to consider each human being as an interchangeable instrument whose response to organizational stimuli is entirely predictable. 6 March and Simon were the first to point out these logical implications of Merton's analysis; the image of the "vicious circle" is ours. '78 Bureaucracy as an Organizational System The Bureaucratic System of Organization *79 This demonstration, however, has so far been more negative than positive. It does not enable us to answer Weber's question about the evolution of industrial society. It suggests that the link between the rational and successful features of a bureaucratic organization and its dysfunctional ones is much more complex than the Taylofian engineers and their contemporary critics thought. It has not, as yet, explored to any extent their interrelations and the conditions of their symbiosis. In order to avoid the paradox, one should analyze more precisely the general etiology of the dysfunctional features of bureaucracy, their limits, and the extent to which the development of modern organization is influenced by such features. In this chapter, we should like, through a re-reading of our data, to examine the possibilities of going beyond this first stage of understanding by considering bureau^ not as dysfunctions, nor even as lecessary dysfunctions of the modern system of organization, but as... rational„parts„o£„the„„"bureaucratic systems of organization." This will enable us to answer, in completely different terms, the question Weber raised about evolution. We shall try to show that a bureaucratic system is restricted in its possible rate of development, and that evolution toward large-scale organizations js^ depends, i to a large extenfTon tne ability of men to break out of the bureaucratic "vicious circle." Before attempting such an exploration, however, we must consider more seriously the decisive contributions made by the sociologists who have used, directly or indirectly, the theory of dysfunctions to analyze bureaucratic phenomena. The Theory of Bureaucratic Dysfunctions: The "Human Relations" Approach to Bureaucracy Interest in the dysfunctions of bureaucracy evolved with the discovery of the human factor and the wide development of the human relations approach in industry. This is not fortuitous. As March and Simon have shown, there is a logical link between the rationale of human relations theories, whatever their kind, and the theory of bureaucratic dysfunctions.7 If we accept the conclusions of the interactionist school or of the " "Bureaucratic" is used here in the popular, pejorative sense. 'James March and Herbert Simon, Organizations (New York: Wiley, 1958), pp. 36-47. We will rely heavily throughout this section on the extremely penetrating analyses of these authors. Lewinian school, or of both, it is as difficult to uphold Max Weber's thesis as to believe in the credo of scientific work organization. When one believes that human activities depend on the feelings and sentiments of the people involved, and on the interpersonal and group relationships that influence them, one cannot expect that imposing economic rationality on them will bring constant and predictable results. The functioning of a bureaucracy can never henceforth be totally explained by the combination of impersonality, expertness, and hierarchy of the "ideal type." If, in addition, one thinks that the most efficient leader of a group is a permissive leader, one must also believe that the best results will not be achieved by the most rational organization in the Weberian sense. They will be attained by the organization in which subordinates participate most in the decision-making process. Sociologists, however, did not break with the Weberian model in the way that "human relations" analysts did with the classical Taylorian model. When Merton pointed the way with his two famous pioneering articles of 1936 and 1940,8 he did not contest directly, the. validity^ He simply indicated that suci^.s£sj:ejn..,QJL .action entails .secondary consequences that run counter to.its objectives and princ he did even this indirectly. Little by little, however, a new scheme was suggested, the rationale of which is more clear today. Merton contends that the discipline necessary for obtaining the sjandard^ required in a bureaucratic organization will bring about a displacement of goals. Bureaucrats will ..show "nt^alist'^'jtjitudes that will make them unable to adjust adequately to the problems they must solve. This will entail the development of a strong esprit de corps at a group level and create a gap between the public and the bureaucracy. Such an analysis is implicitly based upon the following argument. The behavioral rigidity, difficulties of adjustment to the task, and conflicts with the public that exist in a bureaucracy, reinforce the nj^Jforjpritrol and regulation. Thus, finally, the unintended and dysfunctional results of the bureaucratic model tend to reinforce their hold. In human relations terms, dysfunction appears to be the consequence of the resistance of the human factor to standardized behavior that is imposed upon it mechanically. Immediately, however, naive questions emerge: Why do people stick to the mechanical model if it does not bring the desired results? And if they do stick to s Robert K. Merton, "The Unanticipated Consequences of Purposive Social Action," American Sociological Review, I (1936), 894-904, and "Bureaucratic Structure and Personality," Social Forces, XVIII (1940), 560-68. 180 Bureaucracy as an Organizational System it, why is the model a static one, why does it not deteriorate? After all, if the dysfunctional consequences of the model entail the use of more control and more regulation, one should gradually find more and more dysfunction, Merton does not discuss such questions, which is the reason one can say that he remains within Weber's frame of analysis. His aim at the time of writing was only to show that the "ideal type" includes a fair amount of inefficiency and to understand the reason for such a discrepancy between Weber's model and the reality. Many American authors—e.g., Reinhard Bendix, Philip Selznick, Alvin Gouldner, Peter Blau, and Robert Dubin—have followed, in Merton's footsteps. Their empirical studies have confirmed Merton's views. Their considerations have made possible the elaboration of a much clearer and richer scheme for the understanding of what we should to call the "vicious'circle" of" bureaucracy. We will examine here only the works of Selznick- and Gouldner^ the two best-:. elaborated studies. Their theses demonstrate well both the progress realized by, and the inherent limits of, the 'Mysf^cJd^oal-SjdbflQL" Selznick's 1949 study9 deals with the TVA, at that time at the height of its prestige as a model of •.democratic organization and as the symbol of the yearnings of the New Deal. In a way, Selznick's book is similar to the Michels' study; it shows the development. pL. bureaucratic... oligarchy, .behind the _ye.il...of democratic procedure. Selznick's aims, however, are different from, if not the opposite of, those of Michels. Selznick starts with the assumption that bureau-.. cralic pressures must be taken for granted and that the .problem is to..... understand how people manage, to .control......them partially—thus answering the second of our questions about Merton's scheme. Selznick's domain, however, is not the same as Merton's. Selznick uses similar reasoning about unintended results, but applies it to a different part of Weber's ideal type, expertness. He shows how the same kind of vicious circle can develop with expertness and specialization as with hierarchical control and standardization. Specialization grows because decisions have to be made on neutral technical grounds. However, specialization makes the experts more narrow-minded and caste conscious at the same time that outside economic interests.and- pressures t6:3ver|p-iwith their caste policies. These dysfunctions naturally call for more specialization, and a new vicious circle develops.10 ' Philip Selznick, TVA and the Grass Roots (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1949). " We are borrowing this scheme of analysis from March and ^imon, op. cit., pp. 4°-43- The Bureaucratic System of Organization 181 Selznick's most original thinking, however, deals with the problem of the remlfttiffm.. "f.. J^f1..l.Bg!J^H- How does an organization limit the cumulative influence of its dysfunctions? Selznick observed two mechanisms widely used in the TVA. The first concerns the power situation: this is the mechanism: of co-optation, through which outside sectional interests and internal, narrow, expert points of view are given a .share in the decision-making .process—opponents are co-opted to policy-making bodies. The second is the diffusion of a specjalTVA ideology that secures, by its pervasive influence on people in every echelon, the necessary minimum of conformity and loyalty to the organization.11 In this new perspective, bureaucratic dysfunctions are perceived as more diffuse than in the scheme of Merton. They correspond to the rigidity of the organization that may manifest itself in the logic, of specialization as well as in thejogic of centralizatijan. Moreover, Selznick deals not only with the problem of the resistance of the human factor to the mechanistic.. model,, but also with the. problem of power and participation. This second—and, in our opinion, central—problem, however, is analyzed only as regards the possibilities of controlling the development of dysfunctions, rather than as the source of them. Thus Selznick still remains within the Web-erian scheme. Gouldner s study is, in a way, more limited since it does not raise questions outside the hierarchical control pattern delimited by Merton. Nevertheless, it goes one step further in this direction, by showing better the inherent contradiction of the ideal type. Gouldner makes a primary distinction between bureaucracy centered about expertness and bureaucracy centered about punition. He deals (much too rapidly for our taste) with bureaucracy founded on expertness—accepting, on inadequate evidence, that it can escape dysfunction, since the values on which it rests can be accepted by everyone, and the rules that regulate it can be elaborated with enough participation by those who must submit to them. Gouldner's actual subject is punitive bureaucracy. He sees it from three different angles: (1) as a vicious circle around problems of subordination and control; (2) as a behavioral pattern with some latent functions; and (3) as a rational response to an accidental but ineluctable event, succession. The central bureaucratic vicious circle, in Gouldner's view, concerns the problem of close supervision. Impersonal bureaucratic rules evolve because they alleviate the tensions created by subordination "This analysis was first presented in Selznick, "Foundations of the Theory of Organization," American Sociological Review, XIII (1948), 25-35. 182 Bureaucracy as an Organizational System and control; but at the same time they perpetuate the very tensions that bring them into being.12 They especially reinforce the low motivation of the workers that makes close supervision necessary.13 The kterj|Jwctipn,Q£j2!£^u^dc rules is to reduce the tensions that are."3ue, in part, to the differences of values among groups, to the impossibility of elaborating norms acceptable to everyone, and to the steady decrease of friendly informal interactions.14 Gouldner's analysis, at this stage, is not completely satisfactory. At first, it is not easily perceived why values of different groups have to be different, why friendly interactions must decrease, and why acceptable norms cannot be developed. One must seek another underlying factor; and this Gouldner does with his theory of succession. In his final view, the irngerjpjjyaljtyjjEJbK^U^^ is a global organizational response to the problem of succession. This summoning of an external, accidental cause is hot very satisfactory, although the case study is an extremely perceptive one. All modern organizations must face the problems of succession, but they nevertheless have very different and disproportionate kinds of dysfunctions. Gouldner's decisive contribution, however, does not lie in his last and somewhat confused explanatory stage. It is in his earlier and more suggestive interpretation of the role of punitive bureaucratic rules. He has shown how such rules may beusedJn an organization by supervisors and subordinates alike. Both groups take^dvantage or them for punitive purposes and as a bargaining took/inasmuch as each can suspend their application or insist upon it.15 t/Infortunately, Gouldner does not use this insight to broaden his functional analysis. His functional analysis remains partial insofar as it does not integrate the problems of power relationships and the bargaining processes between groups. This time, nevertheless, the Weberian model is at least partially overstepped. Gouldner does not' unders^dJbjS^?^?, features as merely a mearirfpr achieving efficiency; he views them, rather, as a way to"reducetensions within an organization. ,,vv:f " These three examples, the most striking of human relations researches on bureaucracy, demonstrate a substantial moving away from the original Weberian model. These three authors give more, and more place..taihfi.joutine and oppa^vje-aspects of bureaucracy that finally become an autonomous parau^Lsystem^orJiiHrian .Cftusa-tion. But all three—with the partial exception of Selzniclc—tencTto neglect the aspect of rationality and efficiency that is central to any u Gouldner, Patterns of Industrial Bureaucracy, p. 177. "Ibid., V. 178. " Ibid., p. 240. M Ibid., pp. 172-74. The Bureaucratic System of Organization 183 kind of organization. Moreover, they do-not try to • analyze the~ possible interdependence between rationality and dysfunction. This makes it impossible for them to question the dynamic part of the Weberian model, its analysis of the unrelenting evolution toward large-scale bureaucratic organization. Their contribution is inadequate for a discussion of whether or not the resistance of the human factor to the rationalistic push toward more and more efficiency can be successful, or whether or not it can have indirect consequences on organizational rationality itself. Even Gouldner's analysis remains static. At best, it can be described as viewing bureaucratic evolution as a cyclicaLpxocess with alternate bureaucratization and debureau-cratization phases according to the accidents of succession.18 Finally, as March and Simon have pointed out, all these contributions, while setting the stage for further progress, are limited by the human relations theories on human behavior upon which they rest. To go one step further, one must accept the fact--that members of an organization are not governed solely by affective, motivations buf operate as autonomous actors, each one with his own personal strategy*~thls means giving a central place to the power problems we have analyzed in the last chapter. To do this, we shall first examine theproblems.of government raised by the functioning of an organization. \Power relationships^can be considered as the operational consequences of these. The Problem of the Achievement of Conformity Let us accept the main weakness of the sociological theories of bureaucracy as their difficulty in mte^ra.tin^_change and „dey_elop-ment and their reliance on exterior factors to explain the emergence of bureaucratic patterns. Then, in order to go beyond their process-centered analysis, we must raise, in political science terms, the more general question of an organization's government and its minimum requirements. Planned co-operative action is possible only if one can rely on a greafdeal of r^guIarity^Fbehavior on the part of all the participants. In other w6rds,~arvy~orgahTzation members a variable but always substantial amount of conformity. Members will conform partlyjypluntajjly, partly because of coercion. Whatever the 14 In their recent book, Formal Organizations (San Francisco: Chandler, 1961), Peter Blau and W. Richard Scott present a more sophisticated point of view on change, which they tend to see as a much more natural and complex process. This excellent contribution, which I was able to read only after my book had gone to the printer, seems to converge on many points with mine. 184 Bureaucracy as an Organizational System - proportions, the adJsxsi^ be the central problem of an organization's government. When we review more analytically the means used to influence people to conform, we can observe very striking changes in modern times. Only two jpenriiries ago, conformity within an organization was obtained!T&ougFTvery narsh and direct means, with a great deal of open coercion. No regular army could function without the painful and unavoidable experience of drilling that we have all but forgotten today. Supervision by overseers in the eighteenth-century mills was almost equivalent to brutal coercion, and, after all, the galleys were one of the great organizations of their time. Religious or religious-like ideologies partly helped people to internalize organizational aims, but these ideologies themselves were of a fanatic type and terror-ridden. Moreover, conformity com obtained in a specialized and limited way; rather, it required a lifelong total commitment. As a consequence, people were molded in a way that would deeply mark th^eir„,:wM life. Whether they were employees of the Fugger House, members of the Jesuit order, or Prussian grenadiers, they had to devote themselves completely to the organization. Leaving it was equivalent to treason; no large-scale organization could be efficient without such drastic conditions.17 Comparisons with modern organizations may seem overdrawn. Yet they must be made, to bring some perspective into the traditional debate on the standardization and the threatening enslavement of modern man. Modern organizations, in contrast to their predecessors, use a much more, liberal set of pressures. They deal witfujpeople who, through theireducation,have already internalizeoTa^number of basic conformities and a general ability to conform easily to., an organization's way. Then, too, there has been a great Heal of progress in the field of training, and no one feels obliged any longer to make people spend months trying to master the exact observance of petty details. Most important of all, human ...behavior is n^ stood.jndtherefore ^m Because of this, a modern organization does not need the same amount of conformity to get as good results as did earlier organizations. The modern organization can tolerate more deviance, restrict its requirements to a more specialized field, and demand only temporary commitments. For all these reasons, it can and does rely more on indirect and intellectual means to obtain conformity: communication structure and work 17 Sociologists have so far neglected die very important and in some ways crucial body of knowledge to be gained by examining the records of the first large-scale commercial organizations, integrated armies, and religious orders. The theory of organizations could well be enriched by a renewal of such studies. The Bureaucratic System of Organization 185 flow, the technical setting of jobs, economic incentives/and also, perhaps, rational calculus of a higher sort. The punitive aspect of the conformity achievement process has declined. Direct coercion is still in reserve as a last resort, but it is very rarely used, and people apparently no longer have to see it operate often to retain it in their calculations, The contrast is further demonstrated by comparing the quasi-monarchal type that seemingly was necessary for maintaining large-scale organizations at the beginning of the capitalist era with the relatively easy-going and tolerant corporation of the affluent society.18 But even during the last thirty years, there has been a not insignificant change throughout the Western world. Compare, for example, the discipline and conformity of dress and behavior imposed on the sales force of a large department store today with the standards of thirty years ago—a great deal more was required then, and in a much harsher way. Such a reminder makes it possible to understand that, contrary to some easy generalizations, certain "bureaucratic" traits were more likely to appear in earlier organizations than in those of today. Displacement of goals is a case in point. People trained to a rigid conformity, entailing consequences for their whole personalities during their whole lives, are much more likely to indulge in "goal displacement" and "ritualism" than people who are only temporarily specialized—even, as is most often the case, if this specialization is a far narrower one. Rigidity, however, is not engendered only by pressures coming from above. Conformity is not a one-sided process. Subordinates will bargain with their own conformity and use it as a tool with which to bind management. This is just another aspect of the fight for control. Subordinates tacitly agree to play the management game, but they try to turn it to their own advantage and to prevent management from interfering with their independence. When this double pressure is stabilized and leaves very little freedom for adjusting difficulties, then an organization has become deeply rigid. This was the case with the earlier ritualistic clerk who made a point of following his instructions to the letter and ignored the reality with which he had to deal, not only because of his "trained incapacity," but because he needed protection against too harsh treatment in case of error. His "bureaucratic" behavior was not the consequence of the weakness of his own human )nature. It resulted from the way conformity and rationality had to be observed at that time, when there were so few possibilities of intellectually understanding and " Notwithstanding William H. Whyte's and many others' criticism. For a full discussion of their stand see below, pp. 297-98. i86 Bureaucracy as an Organizational System foreseeing complex situations, and thus of devising in advance flexible programs to adjust to them.19 There are comparable modern patterns—e.g., in the Clerical Agency. Supervisors prefer taking routine, inadequate decisions to facing hostile relationships and possible risks of failure. This modern / bureaucratic behavior originates in more complex organizational processes; but these processes, too, are the outcome of bargaining among various groups, and between the organization and these groups, about the way to impose conformity and rationality. jEvigryj)rganization, how^ex, must continually adjust to some kind of/change] It must b^]|exibley To achieve this vague but primary end/it must rely on individual and group ingenuity and cannot discourage it too much.20 The organization must consider this goal when devising ways tOm irflpose^conformity, since it is counter to the other primary goal, 'predictability^ What will be the outcome of ; these two conflicting aims? Its environment, its goals, the kind of fluctuating reality to which an organization must adjust, will be the most important factors to be taken into consideration in this per- , spective. But market uncertainty, as such, is not an omnipotent deterrent to rigidity. Extreme conditions of uncertainty will tend to result in more conformity and rigidity, since trying to adjust to com-pletely unpredictable situations will not be rewarding enough. Too little uncertainty, on the other hand, will make it feasible to pre-scribe-in great detail all possible forms of behavior, thus achieving a ;, high degree of rigidity. There will be a tendency to escape from reality at the two extremes, when reality is too difficult to cope with and when it is no longer a challenge. I It is clear, in any event, that in any kind of organization there is a constant pressure to escape from reality. This tendency corresponds , to what popular sentiment calls "bureaucratic tendencies." Centralization is one of the ways to achieve it; completely impersonal rules are another. Both permit escape from otherwise necessary adjustments. . But in a normal case, evasion cannot go too far. There is a constant feedback of information that permits and even obliges the organization to take account of its errors and to correct them. We shall describe as a "bureaucratic system of organization" any system 10 Even not so long ago, at the beginning of mass production, the product was imposed on the consumer without any possible adjustment. Motorists had to like' their Fords black until it was deemed possible to predict well enough the probable variation of tastes. 20 In the traditional framework of the nineteenth century, it is the entrepreneur ■ who monopolizes the organization's capacity of adjustment. But such a system was feasible only because production units remained small. * The Bureaucratic System of Organization 187 of organization where the feedback process, error-information-correction, does not function well, and where consequently there cannot be any quick readjustment of the programs of action in view of the errors committed. In other words, dijbw^amsrMie^rgan^at^n-is an organization that cannot correctits he}igviqr h% learning from its errors^ Bureaucraticpatterns of action, such as the""imp^rs^bnaKtyrof the rules and the centralization of decision-making, have been so stabilized that they have become part of the organization's self-reinforcing equilibria. Finally, when one rule prevents adequate dealing with one case, its failure will not generate pressure to abandon the rule, but, on the contrary, will engender pressure to make it more complete, more precise, and more binding. The Basic Elements of a Bureaucratic Vicious Circle Let us now try to build a modejj^sjich^ self-reinforcing "bureau-cra_tic_sys.tein'.'-.by using the characteristic traits that emerge from our two case studies. In doing so, we shall, of course, be limited by the specifically French nature of our data. But we shall at least have a starting point, from which we can see whether other models can be imagined and whether there are some traits, some underlying pat-terns,-common to all possible "bureaucratic systems." We shall begin with the basic elements of the bureaucratic "vicious circle" as we observed them in the daily operations of the Clerical Agency and of the Industrial Monopoly. This will give us a static model comparable, in many respects, to the models of Merton and Gouldner. But this first model's main achievement will be to enable us to discuss the system's reactions to change and its own pattern of change. This last step will make it possible to present a general assessment of the self-reinforcing equilibrium. Four basic elements seem to be necessary for the stability of the vicious circle we have observed: the extent of the development of impersonal rules; the centralization of decisions; strata isolation and concomitant group pre^u3rej^.._.the..in