1 Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States: Policies and Practices Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska This volume surveys a new trend in immigration studies, which one could characterize as a turn away from multicultural and postnational perspectives, toward a renewed emphasis on assimilation and citizenship. Much scholarship in the past fifteen years or so, enticed by the discovery of "globalization," has looked at contemporary immigration as obliterating and undermining some traditional principles of nation-states, such as the congruence of political and cultural boundaries and citizenship. In this new orthodoxy, multiculturalism had replaced assimilation as a mode of immigrant integration, and post- or transnational identities, affiliations, and protections had devalued, perhaps even rendered obsolete traditional citizenship. Immigrants were thus depicted as harbingers of a new multicultural and postnational world, in which the national fixity of identity, rights, and organizational capacity had dissolved (for influential statements, see Soysal 1994 and Basch etal. 1994). This volume challenges this orthodoxy in two directions. One looks at state policies, the other at immigrant practices and adjustments. Regarding the first, states have responded to immigration by either t liberalizing their citizenship regimes or upgrading the rights attached to ( citizenship vis-ä-vis inflated non-citizen membership (or "denizenship"). In both cases, citizenship was reaffirmed as the dominant membership principle, and non-citizen membership was either found insufficient or explicitly devalued. In addition, the scope of official multiculturalism ; policies and programs has either been exaggerated in public and academic perception, or, where such policies have actually been in place, there has recently been a covert or overt move away from them. Regarding the practices and adjustment of immigrants and their children there is no evidence that assimilation is not occurring. In fact, one can l 2 Christian foppke and Ewa Momwska observe both: adaptation and use of host-society resources and the maintenance of "transnational" linkages with the society of origin. j Both trends - the resilience of citizenship along with a scaling-down of j multicultural policies, and the simultaneity of assimilation and trans- | nationalism - are explored in this volume through comparisons between Europe and the United States. Let us put more flesh on these propositions. Regarding the revaluation of citizenship, two recent political developments on both sides of the j Atlantic force us to rethink the viability of non-citizen membership for i immigrants. In its Welfare Reform Act of 1996, the United States has excluded legal immigrants from most means-tested federal welfare programs.1 This attempt at revaluing citizenship, which has spurred the largest naturalization wave in US history, demonstrates the inherent i political vulnerability of "postnational" non-citizen status. In its í citizenship reform of 1999, Germany has introduced jus soli citizenship j for second-generation immigrants, in a radical departure from its tradition of citizenship by descent and ethnocultural nationhood (see Hansen in this volume). These developments, though opposite in their restrictive versus liberalizing thrusts, contradict the postnational hypothesis of citizenship in decline. Regarding the reversal of multicultural policies, their prevalence in liberal states has always been exaggerated. There is certainly a widespread ! de-facto multiculturalism in liberal states, which is grounded in their \ commitment to the principles of public neutrality, non-discrimination, j and protection of individual rights. However, in the few cases where official multiculturalism policies were put in place, these policies have recently come under pressure, and there has been a move away from them. This trend is explored in this volume in the case of the Netherlands {see the chapter by Entzinger), which had once been one of Europe's pacesetters for multicultural policies, and is now stressing the importance of Dutch language training and adoption of liberal host-society values. Finally, regarding immigrant practices and adjustments, several studies (particularly in the United States where research on immigration and ethnicity is an established and prolific field across a variety of disciplines) have indicated that immigrants and their children are assimilating on several fronts such as intermarriage, educational ■ attainment, and political behavior. New, however, is that transnational ; identities and involvements, which immigrants have always been \ enmeshed in, are now considered legitimate and no longer repressed by nationalizing states. As the chapters in the second part of this volume Integrating immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 3 show, this has led to complex amalgam structures and dispositions that combine elements of assimilation and transnationalism. The remainder of this introduction maps out the changing direction of state policies and immigrant practices. Liberal nation-states respond to immigration The ubiquitous notion of "integrating" immigrants is surprisingly little reflected on (an exception is the subtle discussion by Favell 2000). It rests on the premise of an already integrated, bounded society, which faces the risk of disintegration and unbinding due to immigration. The underlying picture is that of a society composed of domestic individuals [. and groups (as the antipode to "immigrants"), which are "integrated" | normatively by a consensus and organizationally by a state.2 Postclassical \ sociology, even before the arrival of "globalization," has shown that such a "society" does nowhere exist, except in the imagination of some (especially political) actors. This is not to deny, invoking W.I. Thomas, that this imagination is real in its consequences. However, an academically ,: more adequate picture of modern society is that of a multiplicity of J autonomous and interdependent "fields" (Bourdieu 1989) or "systems" (Luhmann 1997), which engage actors only in specific respects, never in their totality. Politics and the state, which are usually the reference point of "immigrant integration," is at best one among a variety of such fields or systems; and, because modern societies have "neither peak nor center", it is not one that could claim to be any more central than the others (Luhmann 1986: 167-82). From such a systemic, decentered view of society, the very notion of immigrant integration disappears, and the underlying concern for "inclusion" takes on entirely new directions (see Bommes 1999). Immigrants, much like everyone else, are always excluded and included at the same time, excluded as whole persons and included &s sectoral players ľ or agents with specific assets and habitual dispositions within specific \ fields or systems. From such a perspective, the intrinsically polemical i and value-loaded notion of "immigrant" (positive for cosmopolitans, negative for nationalists) simply disappears, and immigrants are conceptually assimilated to other individuals and groupings with similar positions on some critical indices or indicators (such as education, income, employment, political participation, etc.). In this view, from the territorial nowhere of macrosociology, the non-integrated immigrant is a structural impossibility, because from the day, she sets foot in the new society, she is always already "integrated" and engaged in certain 4 Christian foppke and Ewa Morawska fields and systems, be it the (in)formal economy, residential area, family, or ethnic group. j Accordingly, the notion of immigrant integration is an imposition by I the political system, which, unlike all other spheres of society, differentiates the world according to spatial segments (i.e., states), not non-spatial functions, and includes individuals as whole persons (and not just in specific respects) in a mutually exclusive way (usually one cannot be a member of two states at the same time). This is obviously not to suggest that academics stop researching problems of "immigrant integration" -then there would be no point for this book. Instead, the purpose is to make academics aware that one of their presumed analytical categories | ("integration") is really a practical category, taken from the world of ■ politics (on this distinction, see Brubaker 1996).3 Whatever (critical or apologetic) position they may take, in framing their research as one of "integration", immigration scholars inadvertently contribute to the i reproduction of a "regionalist" vision of society as one of bounded ■ nation-states (see Luhmann 1997 I, 166), which is far from the only possible vision, and sociologically even a highly questionable one. Having thus located the non-academic, political origins of the integration concept, it is worthwhile to elaborate on the polemical alternative against which it has been introduced, which is "assimilation." In a second step, we shall point to the shortcomings of a particularly popular brand of integration research, the distinction between so-called "national models" of integration. Whoever uses the word "integration" wishes to say what is allegedly not meant by it, "assimilation."4 The notion of immigrant assimilation was coined during the first wave of industrial-age migration in the late nineteenth century, which occurred against the backdrop of imperialist [ state rivalry, war, and aggressive nation-building. Assimilation meant that Germans in Wisconsin or Pennsylvania, as enemies in World War I, had to give up their fiercely "multicultural" pretensions of retaining their own language, schools, and social habits (Higham 1955); and that ethnically despised Polish labor migrants in the German Ruhr Valley had to trade in their language and "Germanize" their names as the price for their acceptance (Bade 1984). After World War II, Western states desisted from such aggressive nationalizing practices. One reason is that the latter were now epitomized i and delegitimized by defeated Nazism; another is that these states were , now securely sitting on top of thoroughly nationalized societes, as the | combined result of successful industrialization, solidarity-forging wars, and infrastructural incorporation by expanding welfare states. The old Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 5 nationalizing and assimilationist idiom, in a kind of "cultural lag" (Ogburn 1957), and with important national variations, was carried along until the 1960s; but it remained largely rhetorical, and was mostly not accompanied by related policies. Only when the problem of "integrating" postcolonial, labor, and new settler migrants, and especially their offspring, seriously emerged in the 1970s and 1980s, was the postwar liberalism and human-rights discourse applied to the immigration domain, and the notion of integration was born. The new notion of integration, as against old-style assimilation, has two connotations. First, integration is seen as always "intransitive" (see Albers 1994). Immigrants are conceived of not as objects of manipulation and control but as subjects of freely willed integration, for which the state can at best set the parameters, but never guarantee a specific result. Secondly, there is no mandate for immigrants to adopt the substantive culture of the receiving society. The essence of old-style assimilation was cultural assimilation, a sort of alchemy through which an immigrant was transformed into a standardized unit of the state-bearing i nation. The social movements of the 1960s and following explosion of/ "life-style enclaves" (Bellah etal. 1985) and "individualization" (Beck'j 1986) destroyed the old notion of a homogeneous majority population in any given Western state. It is no longer clear what substantive culture is shared in State X by a homosexual, a hooligan, a New Age devotee, or an anti-abortion activist, with the concomitant expectation that the immigrant share it too. From a liberal point of view, which became the point of view in Western states in the second half of the twentieth century, it is a violation of the dignity and autonomy of the individual, citizen or immigrant, to force a substantive culture/ön her, except the thin I , ,. and procedural culture/of liberalism itself. Perhaps also in confrontation | with the Communist alternative, which sought to impose just such a substantive culture (though not a national one) on its subjects, liberal nation-states after World War II did more than ever before to live up to the "liberal" in their name. What, then, does "immigrant integration" consist of in liberal states? A representative answer to this may be found in the newest Report on the Situation of Foreigners in Germany, issued by the Federal Commissioner for Foreigner Affairs (2000). In its section on "integration", one can read ■ that there is no "German monolithic culture" {deutsche Einheitskultiir) [ that immigrants could be asked to share (p. 228). Instead, German society \ is said to consist of a "multiplicity of coexisting life styles." This rules ; out the possibility that "integration" could mean "assimilation." When finally turning from what integration is not to what it might be, only 6 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska fr, , ,. \ two "criteria of integration" are mentioned: "Acceptance of the values of I /! the Constitution (Grundgesetz) and knowledge of the German language" í (ibid,). These are also the two key criteria for naturalizating immigrants, according to the new Citizenship Law of 1999, which ratified an ongoing (though little noticed) departure from making cultural assimilation a prerequisite for citizenship acquisition (see Joppke 1999: ch. 6). ; . ,;;./. ..i,? jjjg German case is no outlier. The final report of the US Commission ~-~~} on Immigration Reform (1997), which had incensed many a liberal for reclaiming the tainted notion of Americanization ("But it is our word, and we are taking it back", p. 26) (see the debate in Pickus 1998), comes to very moderate conclusions as to what "Americanization" consists of: f "the cultivation of a shared commitment to the American values of ; liberty, democracy and equal opportunity" (ibid.), along with a reinforced emphasis on the "rapid acquisition of English" (p. 37). In addition, and ; in contrast to its tainted predecessor, Americanization this time round is not to be understood as a one-sided imposition of the norms of majority society, but as a mutual and reciprocal process. This implicitly | acknowledges that in a liberal context integration cannot but be intransi-i Jive; "Immigration presents mutual obligations. Immigrants must accept the obligations we impose - to obey our laws, to pay taxes, to respect other cultures and ethnic groups. At the same time, citizens incur obligations to provide an environment in which newcomers can become fully participating members of our society" (US Commission on Immigration Reform 1997: 28). The German and American examples demonstrate the thin meaning | of immigrant integration in liberal nation-states: language acquisition | plus a commitment to the political values that constitute a liberal j democracy, independently of its concrete territorial incarnation. However, the abhorring of the old, cuIture^foc.used "assimilation" approach had one unfortunate consequence. Understood structurally, as the socioeconomic equalization of the life-chances between immigrants and native population (in employment,^rrico^měi^^úcaťfonrefcO, "assimilation" had to remain the normative horizon of immigrant integration. Only, and reinforced by the difference-oriented rhetoric that proliferated in the 1980s and much of the 1990s, there was no language available to articulate this ongoing concern. If recently there has been a "return of assimilation" in a number of Western states (see Brubaker in this volume), this is because the underlying socioeconomic equality concern had never disappeared. The popular notion of national models of immigrant integration has obscured the similarities of integration approaches and assimilation Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 7 concerns across liberal states.5 A particularly popular contrast was the one between French assimilationism and "Anglo-Saxon" multiculturalism. There is not much substance to this line of reasoning, in which academics have simply become captive of political surface rhetoric. As Martin Schain (1999) has convincingly shown, the allegedly assimilationist French state became involved in a de facto politics of multicultural recognition at the local level, driven by the sheer need to find ethnic interlocutors and sounding-boards for its policies. Moreover, in the new "Republican" consensus emerging in the 1990s, the very notion of * assimilation has been discredited, and replaced by that of integration. \ In doing so, France embraced the liberal Western mainstream approach toward immigrant integration, which is to tolerate cultural difference in private and associational life, but refuse to give it public status. This is encapsulated in the definition of integration suggested by the Haut Conseil ä ľíntégration (which the French government set up in the early 1990s to find ways out of the notorious "foulard affair", see Favell 1998: ch. 6): "Ľíntégration consiste ä susciter la participation active ä la société tout entiěre de ľensemble des femmes et des hommes appelés ä vivre durablement sur notre sol en acceptant sans arriere-pensees que [ subsistent des spécificités notamment culturelles, mais en mettant ľaccent sur les ressemblances et les convergences dans ľégalité des droits et des devoirs" (Haut Conseil 1993: 8). Admittedly, this amounts to little more than giving a new name to what France had been doing all along (except for a brief interlude of difference-supporting "insertion" in the early 1980s). But the rhetorical move away from the now tainted "assimilation" concept, which France more stubbornly than any other Western state had long subscribed to, is still significant, because its approach now is also nominally indistinguishable from that of most other Western states.6 On the opposite side, there has never been a uniform "Anglo-Saxon" multiculturalism. Britain (more precisely England) borrowed some of its race-relations framework from the United States, but then crucially transformed the latter's civil-rights orientation into one of public order, while - among other things - firmly turning its back on US-style affirmative action (see Joppke 1999: ch.7). The United States, which in fact has always taken a hands-off approach in matters of immigrant integration and certainly has never adhered to an explicit "national model", may appear "multicultural" for the very homegrown and political purposes of a French intellectual (e.g., Todd 1994; and critical Fassin 1999). If compared with explicitly multicultural Canada, the US is often taken as the assimilationist opposite (e.g., Kymlicka 1998: 21). Once we abandon 8 Christian foppke and Ewa Morawska I the misleading "national model" talk, we discover only the rather thin I and uniform "integration" requisites of liberal states, plus a plethora I of con text-specific ad hoc policies, utterly devoid of an underlying "philosophy" of integration.7 We now turn to a discussion of two important recent changes in liberal states' integration policies: the scaling-down of official multiculturalism; and the revaluation of citizenship. Decline of official multiculturalism Regarding multicultural policies, one must distinguish between de facto multiculturalism, which is required fay the logic of liberal states, and official multiculturalism, in which states have deliberately and explicitly recognized and protected immigrants as distinct ethnic groups. De facto f multiculturalism has become a pervasive reality in liberal, immigrant-/ receiving states. It has many facets, from the principled protection of rights | to pragmatic concessions in the interest of public health or security. The individual rights and liberties protected by the constitutions of liberal states have allowed immigrants qua individuals to find recognition / andprotection for their distinct;cultural practices. Independent judiciaries have been instrumental for this. Consider orie typical court decision on a particularly sensitive issue, the physical co-education of Muslim girls. In the Swiss canton of Zürich, usual practice was to excuse from j co-educational swimming lessons for religious reasons only more I mature (high school) female Muslims. Against this, the Swiss Federal Court decided in June 1993 to grant such excuse already for very young (primary school) Muslim girls. As in all such cases, the Court had to balance in its decision opposite legal and moral principles and interests: the religious and educational freedoms protected by the domestic constitution and the international conventions that Switzerland subscribed to; and the state interest in an orderly public education, which entailed the securing of equal chances for everyone, Muslim girls included. The Court reasoning contains striking, but from our perspective predictable, language: Members of other countries and cultures, who reside in Switzerland, are obliged to respect the domestic legal order like any native Swiss. However, there is no legal obligation for them to adopt (Swiss) customs and ways of life. One cannot deduce from the principle of integration a legal rule that forces (immigrants) to restrict their religious or cultural beliefs in a disproportionate (unverhältnismässig) way (quoted in Albers 1994: 987). Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 9 German courts have reached very similar conclusions on exempting Muslim girls from certain public school requirements, attesting to an "intransitive" (in effect, multicultural) understanding of immigrant integration (ibid.). On the pragmatic pole, states have often resorted to de facto multiculturalism in the pursuit of their own interests. Examples are mother-tongue education, which followed the opposite purposes of either keeping the return option open or allowing immigrants to acquire the domestic language and domestic "rules of the game" more easily; foreign language instructions and advisory services in the public health, social service, or penal sectors, for the sake of a smoother public policy implementation; or the recognition and engagement of ethnic organizations as sounding boards for grievances in need of correction by the state (on this, see Schain 1999). Even at the level of political rhetoric, de facto multiculturalism is firmly in place. Consider the case of Quebec, the secessionist French-speaking province of Canada, which shows that in a world of liberal states even an extreme nation-building project must bow_to„.the \ dominant rhetoric of cultural pluralism (see Carens 2000: ch. 5). Because of its nation-building (and thus monocultural) ambition, Quebec has always rejected the official multiculturalism practiced since the early 1970s by the Canadian government. Moreover, as a partial price for its accommodation within a federal Canada, Quebec has achieved complete authority over policies on immigrant integration. However, the central document underlying Quebec's integration policy, entitled Vision: A Policy Statement on Immigration and Integration (1990), is rather modest in scope and tone. It expects immigrants to respect the values of "democracy" and "pluralism," which are obviously not specific to Quebec, but generic to all liberal democracies. This includes the multicultural concession that people in Quebec, immigrant or not, are free to "choose their own lifestyles, opinions, values and allegiances to interest groups within the limits defined by the legal framework" (quoted in Carens 2000:117). The only expression of Quebec's "distinct society" pretension is the requirement that immigrants (like all others) adopt French as the common language of public life. However, language acquisition is the small rest of distinctly cultural ' adaption that every liberal state, not just Quebec, demands of its newcomers. As Joseph Carens concludes from the case of Quebec, "any defensible version of liberal democracy today entails a commitment \ to pluralism that inevitably opens the door to multiculturalism in ''■■ some form" (ibid., p. 139). 10 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska Most liberal states have evidently avoided the opposite poles of "extreme differentialism" and "extreme assimilationism" (Zolberg and Woon 1999: 30), settling instead for a middle position of de facto multiculturalism. However, this middle position looks rather different regarding language and religion, perhaps the central multicultural claims in the United States and Europe, respectively. Regarding religion, liberal immigrant-receiving states have shown more inclination toward pluralism than regarding language. The reason is simple: while a differentiation between church and state is possible, and in fact increasingly a reality in liberal states, the state cannot but engage in linguistic choices, leaving less space for pluralism in this domain. At the same time, requiring an immigrant to acquire another language is less demanding than asking her to acquire another religion (or asking her to stop practicing her own), because every individual can speak several languages, but can adhere to only one religion. Language assimilation is therefore more compatible with liberal values than religious assimilation. Liberal states have, in fact, shown themselves adept in providing space for immigrant-imported religions, most importantly Islam, either through prolonging a historically entrenched separation of religion and í state (as in France and the United States), or through extending historical I church-state linkages to non-Christian religions (as in Germany, the 1 Netherlands, or the United Kingdom) (for Western Europe, see Bauböck I 1999). In any case, the accommodation of religious difference epitomizes ■ the inevitable trend toward de facto multiculturalism in liberal states: "(T)he constitutional obligations of liberal regimes to respect religious freedom move contemporary possibilities away from assimilation toward the pluralist pole" (Zolberg and Woon 1999: 14). Official multiculturalism goes beyond de facto multiculturalism in engaging the state in the recognition and protection of immigrants as distinct ethnic groups. In contrast to de facto multiculturalism, which can be found in every liberal state qua liberal state, official multiculturalism has been much less widespread. Prominent examples are Canada, Australia, Sweden, or the Netherlands. Interestingly, the entrenchment of de facto multiculturalism contrasts sharply with the precariousness of official multiculturalism, which has come under pressure everywhere, and in Europe is even at the point of disappearing. A number of reasons is responsible for the precarious nature of official multiculturalism. At the normative level, official multiculturalism is difficult to defend. In Will Kymlicka's version (1998: 38f), official multiculturalism is about "renegotiating" the terms of state-imposed integration. But the meaning of this is unclear. For Kymlicka, individuals need "societal cultures" (which Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 11 he defines, much like "nations," by a shared language and territorial rootedness) as context for free and meaningful choices (Kymlicka 1995: 76). States are the guardians of such societal cultures, that is, Gellnerian nation-builders - even today, and even in that part of the world where such nation-building has originated in the age of industrialism, and where it may be presumed to have come to a successful end by now.8 Key to Kymlicka's defence of multiculturalism is the argument that, contrary to their complacent self-image, liberal states cannot be culturally neutral; however implicitly, the latter must favor the societal culture of the state-bearing nation (for instance, in their language policies). This amounts to a considerable imposition on immigrants, who carry with them (and seek to stick to) their own societal cultures. Because the state cannot be neutral, fairness commands to grant immigrants certain cultural rights, mostly in the form of exemptions from general laws that bear the mark of the majority culture (such as Sunday closing laws). However, in voluntarily leaving their homelands, immigrants have also "waived" the right to their culture, and they have consented to adopt the one of the receiving state and thus to become "integrated" (ibid., p. 96). As Joseph Carens (2000: 57) has remarked, it is not clear from this position "why immmigrants are entitled to any special rights to maintain their distinctive cultural commitments". Accordingly, Kymlicka's defence of cultural rights for immigrants is rather minimalist and ad hoc. This is especially visible in his peculiar defence of Canadian multiculturalism. On the one hand, Canadian multiculturalism policy is presented as "just one small piece of the pie," while "other policies" (on naturalization, education, job training, human rights and anti-discrimination law, civil service employment, health and safety, etc.) are said to be "the major engines of integration" (Kymlicka 1998: 24). On the other hand, this smallish policy ("a drop in the bucket compared with the billions of dollars spent on policies that directly or indirectly promote integration," p. 38) is held responsible for everything positive happening in the integration field since the adoption of official multiculturalism in 1971, such as increasing naturalization and intermarriage rates: "The two countries that lead the world in the integration of immigrants (Canada and Australia) are countries with official multiculturalism policies" (p. 21f). It is unclear how a "drop in the bucket" policy could have made Canada a world leader in immigrant integration. At the same time, the pressure that Canadian multiculturalism is currently facing is presented as a mere communication failure by the federal government, which, among other things, has been silent on the 12 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska "limits of tolerance" (ibid., ch. 4). In Kymlicka's view, Australia has been much better at explicating these limits. The central document of Austrialian multiculturalism, entitled National Agenda for a Multicultural Australia (1989), is indeed framed by an "overriding commitment to the nation" (Zappala and Castles 2000: 52), which includes the duty to accept the Constitution and its underlying values and the recognition of English as the national language. However, this has not prevented a new Liberal-National Party Coalition, after their election victory in 1996, to abolish the government's Office for Multicultural Affairs, in response to a populist groundswell against multiculturalism. This shows that official multiculturalism's difficulties must have deeper roots than a communication failure on the part of the government. Overall, Kymlicka's defence of Canadian multiculturalism is much i better at refuting the widespread charge that it has produced ethnic ; strife and separatism than at showing that it has helped the cause of ; immigrant integration; this causality, though central to his defence, he ■ does not establish. In assessing why official multiculturalism is everywhere in difficulties, it is important to distinguish its fundamentally different meanings in the new settler nations of Canada and Australia and in Europe. Multiculturalism in Canada and Australia is directed at everyone, not only : \ immigrants.9 It provides a national self-understanding for former British j colonies, which - in contrast to the United States - lack independent | founding myths and which faced a void once a self-definition in terms of British heritage and surJjectŠhíp was no longer viable. This universal thrust of new-settler multiculturalism is visible in Canada's Multiculturalism Act of 1988, which mandates the government to "recognize and promote the understanding that multiculturalism reflects the cultural and racial diversity of Canadian society and (to acknowledge) the freedom of ail members of Canadian society to preserve, enhance and share their cultural heritage" (quoted in Kymlicka 1998: 185; emphasis supplied). Its linkage with national self-understanding helps entrench official multiculturalism against its current opposition. / By contrast, in Europe official multiculturalism is targeting immigrants | only, seeking to transform them into ethnic minorities. This makes / official multiculturalism more vulnerable here than in Canada or Australia. This is not to say that such policies in Europe do not flow from national traditions. On the contrary. In Sweden and the Netherlands, the integration of immigrants as officially designated collectivities simply extended their long-engrained corporatist modes of organizing polity and society. However, hypostasizing these policies as "corporatist Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 13 membership models" (Soysal 1994: 36-38) overlooks their significant changes over time, in fact, their eventual abandonment. Sweden started its official multiculturalism policy in 1975, as a high-minded and "progressive" departure from continental Europe's bickering over keeping or sending back its guestworkers. Its three cornerstones were "equality," "freedom of choice," and "partnership." The distinctly multicultural element in this Immigrant and Minority Policy was freedom of choice; it became enshrined in a new paragraph in the constitution, which mandated the state to protect aňcTfurťhěr the cultural identity of Sweden's ethnic, linguistic, and religious minorities. Every immigrant group whose size exceeded 1000 persons qualified as "ethnic minority," which secured them mother-tongue education, own TV and radio stations, and state support for ethnic newspapers, periodicals, and other cultural activities. Interestingly, this state support for ethnic minorities centered exclusively on cultural affairs, because with respect to welfare and social services immigrants were included as individuals, not as groups, reflecting the universalism of the Swedish welfare state. The move away from the progressive beginnings occurred in several steps. A parliamentary inquiry in the mid-1980s came to the curious, yet legally correct, conclusion that under international law citizenship status was a prerequisite for official minority status (see the general overview in Jackson Preece 1998). Accordingly, immigrants could be a minority like the native Saami or Lapps only at the price of a radical deviation from international law and practice, which Sweden was not prepared to undertake. This led to the renaming of the Immigrant and Minority Policy as the Immigrant Policy. However, not just legal reasoning was behind this name change. By the mid-1980s, most newcomers were no longer "immigrants" originating from a few Nordic or southern European countries, but "refugees" originating from all corners of the globe. To further increase their already considerable cultural distance from Swedish society by means of state policy came to appear as a strange thing. The parliamentary inquiry therefore concluded that the proper interpretation of the "freedom of choice" clause of the 1975 policy was state neutrality: the state was not to enforce assimilation,Hbut neither was it to oppose such assimilation in principle. At the same time, the source-diversity of the new immigrants led the government to stress the limits of "freedom of choice," and that it had become necessary "to express more clearly the basic views of Swedish society on a number of issues of principle" (quoted in Soininen 1999: 690). A more decisive turn away from official multiculturalism occurred in the 1990s, against the backdrop of skyrocketing unemployment rates for 14 Christian Joppke and Ewa Momwska immigrants and deepening ethnic cleavages10 as well as a general questioning of welfarism and retreat of central state planning. In the wake of a parliamentary review of immigrant policy, a new "integration" policy was put in place, along with a renaming of the "immigrant minister" into "integration minister". While the new policy rhetorically sticks to { the 1975 framework of equality, freedom of choice, and cooperation, the multicultural thrust of the original policy has all but disappeared. Immigrants are no longer to be integrated as a collectivity, but as individuals, colored by a neoliberal discourse of self-sufficiency. Instead of being set apart as an ethnic minority, immigrants are now to "acquire the Swedish tools which can be needed to manage on one's own in Swedish society" (quoted in Soininen 1999: 692). The message is clear: the earlier stress on cultural pluralism had blatantly ignored the socioeconomic rift opening up between immigrants and the domestic population, and tackling this rift meant making immigrants indistinguishable from the domestic population (in this sense, to "assimilate" them) - witness that the very notion of "immigrant" has practically disappeared in the new Swedish "integration" discourse. The Dutch move away from official multiculturalism occurred somewhat later, but more extreme than in Sweden (see also Entzinger in this volume). The Dutch "ethnic minorities policy" (Minderhedennota) was born in 1983, interestingly, as a simple inversion of the earlier policy to keep the return option open. Eight groups were officially designated as minorities: Turks, Moroccans and Tunisians, Surinamese, Dutch Antilleans, Moluccans, south Europeans, refugees, and Gypsies. Excluding Chinese and Pakistani from this list betrayed the functional nature of this ethnically rather inconsistent mix: only groups "who did not participate on an equal base in Dutch society" (Amersfoort 1999) were included. The key notion in this minority policy was "emancipation", and not within : Dutch society, but ~ in line with the tradition of pillarization - within separate institutions, such as religious schools and "ethnic broadcasting, all financed by the state. " However, the pillarization of immigrants ~ from the start a strange rehash of a long dead mode of social organization (see Lijphart 1968) -did not work as foreseen (see Entzinger 2000: 19f). First, assigning public status to ethnic minorities is fine as long as there are only a few of them. Once the source countries multiplied, particularly after the onset of mass asylum-seeking, it became impossible to prpvide all of them with an own infrastructure. Moreover, state funding for ethnic minorities only helped feed a small elite of ethnic activists, along witli'ihfíghtš and factionalisms, while doing little to improve the lives of ordinary integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 15 immigrants. Secondly, the old (and by now defunct) pillarism had rested on elite cooperation, which in turn was enabled by a sense of being members of one nation. This element of consensus-building was neglected by the ethnic minority policy. Accordingly, Dutch official multiculturalism yielded only "segregation" and "exclusion" (Entzinger 2000: 20). As in Sweden, diversifying migrant profiles and increasing socioeconomic disparities moved Dutch policy away from official multiculturalism, toward a "policy of obligatory integration" that by far outpaled the Swedish development (Entzinger 1998: 115). It rests on a new understanding of multiculturalism as a social fact, rather than a goal to ' be achieved by means of state policy. Instead of being; fuelled by statist official multiculturalism, the centrifugal forces of de facto multiculturalism í are to be countered by a centripetal emphasis on civic communalities. An expression of this is the Law_piLtS&OyLcJnIegration of Newcomers, passed in 1998. Already before that, most programs specifically targeting immigrants were either discontinued, or made accessible to disadvantaged people in general, not only immigrants. Tellingly, the few remaining programs that explicitly target immigrants are not "multicultural", but designed to insert immigrants in Dutch society. The 1998 law imposes 600 hours of mandatory civics and language classes on all new non-EU migrants. In the words of Hah Entzinger, who helped bring it about, the hew law reflects the idea "that the multicultural society can only function on the basis of some minimal convictions shared by all of its members" (Entzinger 1998: 116).11 Revaluation of citizenship The Dutch policy of obligatory integration made inburgering, in the sense of civic integration, the focus of state policy regarding immigrants. The German translation of the Dutch word inburgering - Einbürgerung - refers to a closely related concern: to make immigrants citizens. For many years, European states, Germany and the Netherlands included, pursued a strategy of approximating the status of alien to that of citizen, thus minimizing the privileges attached to citizenship. In the Netherlands, this was part of the progressive Minderhedennota of 1983, and materializing -among other things - in the granting of local voting rights to foreigners in 1985. In Germany, this strategy was more implicitly and defensively pursued in order to protect its ethnically exclusive citizenship regime (see Joppke 1999: ch. 6). Some scholars have concluded from the upgrading of alien status in postwar European states, to a certain degree also in the United States, 16 Christian joppke and Ewa Morawska that national citizenship has become less relevant for the integration of immigrants.12 In Soysal's (1994: 3) concise formulation, guestworkers in postwar Europe have become integrated, not as "citizens" but as "persons," on the basis, not of national norms and legitimatory discourses but of a global human rights regime: "This new model, which I call post-national ... derive(s) from transnational discourse and structures celebrating human rights as a world-level organizing principle." While its general assumptions are questionable (see Joppke 1998, 2002), the postnational membership model has a limited empirical relevance for first-generation immigrants, for whom the upgrading of alien status was originally devised, also with an eye on keeping their return option open. And it adequately reflects the spirit in which European states r particularly have sought to integrate immigrants through the 1980s. | However, once the problem of integrating thejecond and third generation í of settled guestworkers moved to the fore, the deficits of postnational \ membership became obvious. The violent outbursts against "foreigners" " in postunity Germany did not distinguish between asylum-seekers and "Turks" born and raised in Germany. The increasing association between crime and. immigration, very much a phenomenon of the 1990s, moved some populist governments, like the conservative Land //government of Bavaria, to simply send pack inconvenient young ífé.delinquents^even though they may have never seen the country they s were sentTback to - no postnational membership could comejo their j rescue, because protection from expulsion has everywhere remained the privilege of citizens. In short, the problem of integrating second- and third-generation immigrants has launched a massive trend toward the revaluation of citizenship in European states, which cannot be accommodated within the postnational membership model (see the overview in Hansen and Weil 2001). While happening on both sides of the Atlantic, the current revaluation of citizenship has taken rather opposite directions in each (see Joppke 2000). In the United States, the trend has been toward the tightening of citizenship, in the context of a historically inclusive citizenship regime. One expression of this is the attempt to restrict the access to citizenship ~ abolish jus soli for the children of illegal immigrants, prohibit dual citizenship, tighten the naturalization requirements, etc. Interestingly, í all these campaigns have failed. Why? One reason is that a more exclusive | citizenship regime would violate contemporary liberal norms; a second | is that exclusive citizenship would mean the uprooting of a national tradition, and challenge America's self-understanding, uncontested since the mid-1960s, as a nation of immigrants. Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 17 More successful has been a second expression of the American trend toward the tightening of citizenship, the tying of more substantive benefits > , y and privileges to the status of citizen. This is the thrust of the 1990s ' l welfare reform, which excludes legal immigrants from most federal (and, -:.( some state) welfare programs.13 Tt~reverses a universal trend in liberal states toward approximating the status of alien to that of citizen. However, this particular way of revaluing citizenship is specific to the United States, because no other liberal state disposes of an equivalent to the "plenary power" doctrine that immunizes the immigrant-related policiesotThe'federaTgovernment from judicial scrutiny. The exclusion r} of immigrants from welfare is US-specific in yet another sense: it reinvig- -orates the traditional view of immigrant admission as a "covenant" between immigrant and American society, whose sustained openness is exchanged against requesting immigrants to be self-sufficient.14 The "deeming" provision of the 1996 Illegal Immigration and immigrant Responsibility Act is, after all, no novelty of the 1990s, but a (mostly dormant) part of federal immigration law since its inception in the 1880s. In Europe, the revaluation of citizenship has taken the opposite direction, toward more inclusive citizenship, in the context of historically exclusive citizenship laws.'5 Throughout the 1990s, most European states have reformed their citizenship laws, to make it easier for long-settled j migrants and their children to acquire the citizenship of the host | society. With the exception of Austria, Greece, and Luxembourg, all i member states of the European Union now provide a right to citizenship for second-generation immigrants (see Hansen 1998). Germany, previously the paragon of "postnational" immigrant integration, had been a member of this club already before its wholesale reform of citizenship law in 1999 (see Joppke 1999: ch. 6). The burgeoning literature on immigration and citizenship is marked by two extreme theoretical positions. Brubaker (1992), who started the entire genre, was an argument in favor of citizenship traditionalism, according to which there was persistent divergence between states' national citizenship laws and policies. Soysal (1994) argued that national citizenship was in decline everywhere, and that there was convergence across states toward postnational membership schemes. As opposite as they seem, in certain cases (such as pŕe-uhity Germany) both theoretical positions may well complement one another (see Joppke 1999: ch. 6). However, the current revaluation of citizenship, particularly in Europe, proves both of these extreme positions wrong. Instead of simply reaffirming national citizenship traditions or of devaluing citizenship as 18 Christian foppke and Ewa Morawska such, the postwar immigration experience (among other factors) has | launched a trend toward the de-ethnicization of citizenship. This 1 means that citizenship in Europe is becoming a bit like citizenship in I America,-, attributed by birth on territory and constituted by political values rather than by ethnicity. One element of de-ethnicized citizenship is the resurgence of territorial jus soli citizenship in Europe. Pioneered by revolutionary France, ethnic citizenship, attributed at birth jur^ sanguinis, had once been associated with the modem invention of democracy and nationhood, replacing ] the feudal principle of jus soli, according to which the products of the { soil, be it crops or peoplepwere the property, of .the lard. This preference for ethnic citizenship was reinforced in the Age of Empire, in which sending states had an interest in maintaining links with the millions of settlers and emigrants overseas. In the postwar context of immigration, however, jus sanguinis rules, which keep labor migrants out of the citizenry over generations, created a severe deficit of democratic incju-siveness (see Koslowski 2000: ch. 4). This is why previously exclusively jus sanguinis states came to complement their jus sanguinis rules with jus soli rules, examples being Spain, Belgium, the Netherlands, and most recently Germany.16 This has important long-term implications for the underlying ideas of nationhood. To the degree that mere birth on territory confers citizenship, the state-constituting citizenry (i.e., the nation) can no longer be conceived of in ethnic terms. Instead, the latter is being transformed into a politically constituted, territorial body, ä ľamérkaine. A second element of de-ethnicized citizenship is the increasing toler-', /;; ation of dual citizenship in Europe. This is expressed in the Council of Europe's new nationality convention of 1997, which permits the signatory 'x ''■ v states to tolerate dual nationality in the interest of better immigrant ; integration. The old nationality convention of 1963, whose outlawing of dual nationality was binding only among its European signatories and thus allowed these states to retain or even build dual nationality provisions with a plethora of extra-European (mostly postcolonial) states, had become patently anachronistic in the age of European unification. It is important to realize, however, that dual citizenship is an ambivalent and contested phenomenon, fiercely rejected by some states (Denmark, Austria), rhetorically rejected but tacitly tolerated by others (Germany, the Netherlands), and openly endorsed by a third group of states _ -cy (United Kingdom, France). And it is a Jamasjfaced^h^n^Tierion: what / appears as de-ethnicization from the perspective of immigrant-receiving states, means re-ethnicization from the perspective of sending states, such as Mexico, Turkey, Columbia, Equador, or the Dominican Republic, Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 19 all of which have recently endorsed dual citizenship in order to maintain links with their ethnic diasporas abroad. This ambivalence is well captured by Rey Koslowski: "Dual nationality may just as easily signify the retention of homeland political identity as political incorporation into the host society, just as easily signify the possession of multiple political identities or the lack of any political identity at all" (Koslowski 2000: 154). A third element of de-ethnicized citizenship is the relaxed attitude toward minority identities and ways of life in liberal states, which we discussed above as "de facto multiculturalism." To be a citizen of a liberal state no longer connotes membership in a particular cultural community; the only "culture" that citizens are asked to share is the "political culture of liberalism itself" (Perry 1995: 114). An expression of thisls the "thinning" of hafufahzatlbn requirements in liberal states. Germany, for instance, which until recently had subjected even its German-born applicants to an excruciating individual assimilation test, in the early 1990s lowered the threshold to certain generic residence and schooling requirements, granting citizenship as-of-right if these requirements were fulfilled. Interestingly, however, the lowering of the hurdle for as-of-right naturalization from fifteen to eight years of residence in the 1999 Citizenship Law was accompanied by a tightening of the language requirements, and advocates of the old assimilation idea - like the state government of Bavaria - have tried to save the latter through making the language hurdle exceedingly difficult to pass.17 Germany, in fact, which is still today considered by many as the proverbially ethnic state, much like Israel or japan (e.g., Coleman and Harding 1995: 51), is a prime example of de-ethnicization, introducing conditional jus soli for second-generation immigrants in its new Citizenship Law of 1999, tacitly tolerating dual citizenship in administrative practice (though not in official political discourse), and rejecting the idea of a German Leitkultur (dominant culture) to which immigrants had to adjust.18 De-ethnicized citizenship is certainly not happening everywhere. It is an SícTú^ively ^Western pfiehomenon, reflecting the emergence of a North-Atlantic "security community" (Deutsch etal. 1957). Its true galvanizer is not so much immigration as the transformation of the North-Atlantic region from a Hpbbesian. zone of war info a Lockean zone of trade. The development of citizenship was historically tied to the development of nations as war-making bodies, and in certain parts of the world (like the Middle East or south-eastern Europe) this linkage has remained disturbingly vital. With the end of war in the Lockean 20 Christian foppke and Ewa Morawska zone, the "national" component of national citizenship, rather than . disappearing, is undergoing a transformation, from ethnic to civic-territorial. In a word, citizenship is everywhere becoming "Americanized," constituted by political values rather than by confrontation with a hypqstasized OtKěfrCitižěhship is one domain in which liberal states are finally getting serious about the "liberal" in their name. Transnational immigrants: De-anchored or integrating? Turning from state policies to migrant practices and adjustments, we take issue with some claims raised in the recent literature on "transnational" migration. The first is this: "One of the major changes in migration patterns is the growth of transnational populations anchored (socially and culturally as well as physically) neither at their places of origin nor at their places of destination" (Vertovec and Cohen 1999: xiii). According / to the proponents of the ^w^transnationalism thesis^/p^resent-day immigrants' regular engagement in social, cultural, and political "transnational spaces", that transcend or escape nation-state boundaries is a phenomemon without precedent in the history of cross-border migrations - the result of, and contributor to, the accelerated globalization of the contemporary world. A second, related claim is that the location of immigrants' commitments in translocal spaces above and beyond the boundaries of the receiving state effectively undermines the assimilation model of incorporating newcomers and their children (or "ethnics"). Thirdly, this transnationalism "from below" is said to work in tandem with globalizing forces "from above" that have been weakening the controlling and legitimating powers of the receiving state.(Good overviews of these arguments can be found in Vertovec and Cohen 1999 and Hirschman etal 1999). As we shall demonstrate in the remainder of this chapter, none of these claims raised by the new transnationalists is supported by evidence; or, more accurately, each of them requires a significant qualification that changes the thrust of the argument. First, present-day immigrants' transnationalism is not as new as its proponents represent it - in fact, in many important aspects it resembles economic, social, and political translocal involvements of past cross-border travelers. Secondly, transnational commitments of immigrants or ethnics do not preclude and actually often coexist with their economic, political, and cultural integration into the host society. Finally, rather than being disempowered by the transnational participation of its foreign-stock population, the Integrating immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 21 receiving state continues to influence the intensity, forms, and directions of transnationalism. The new-old immigrant transnationalism Although they did not cail it "transnationalism," immigration historians have extensively documented the enduring bT-national socioeconomic and political involvements and cultural identities of nearly ail American immigrant groups in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Historical evidence shows that the new transnationalists' claims about 1 ^ the novelty of multinational connections of present-day immigrants is \ '17 inaccurate on at least three accounts. First, the view is incorrect that, unlike present-day multiple, circular, and return migrations, turn-of-the-twentieth-century international travels rälsoacross the Atlantic, were singular journeys from one sedentary space to ..another. Secondly,., the perception is unfounded that, as one-way transplants, earlier migrations (.f>ä were permanent ruptures with home-country affairs, irrevocably dividing past and present lives of the immigrants, whereas present-day shuttlers' lifeworlds span their home and host societies in new transnational spaces. The majority of migrants across the European continent (the bulk of cross-border movement in that period) were repeat seasonal travelers, and no fewer than 35-45 percent of south and east Europeans | who crossed the Atlantic returned home at least once (Wyman 1993). i Both temporary migrants and those who settled abroad permanently maintained close economic, social, and cultural ties with their home-country communities. Thirdly, the view is inaccurate that the emergence of these new transnational spaces has created a complex new sphere of politics, supposedly nonexistent in the past, in which political leaders in the home countries and immigrants in the transplanted communities abroad engage each other and the host-country establishment. Turn-of-the -twentieth-century sending states in south and east Europe actively involved immigrant communities abroad in their nätwn-büilding projects: positively by supporting (home) national associations and the encompassing national identity formation, and negatively by attempting to control the emergence of national consciousness and organizations among immigrants. (For these "new transnational!st" claims see, e.g., Basch etal. 1994; also Lie 1995; Portes 1997; for historical rebuttals, see Gerstle 1997; Guttierez 1997; Foner 1997). Although not a new phenomenon in the history of international migration, contemporary immigrant transnationalism, of course, is not an exact replica of the old, but shaped by a different configuration of circumstances. First, because of rapid advances in communication and 22 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska transportation technology - the so-called "global compression of time f and space" - present-day transnational connections maintained by I immigrants are more>.dénse and intense than those in the past. Second, i these connections are much more varied or plural in form and content S because contemporary immigrants themselves are much more diverse ( in regional origin, racial identification, gender, and home-country socioeconomic background. In the host society, immigrants also differ in their legal status, the sector of the economy in which they are employed, and their mode of acculturation to the dominant society. Third, the public discourse and juridical systems of both the sending and receiving states are today much.more tolerant of diversity than, theywere in the .past. Earlier-wave immigrants and their children were "closet transnationalists," subject to exclusionary demands from home and host states regarding their national commitments. By contrast, legitimate "public" options for identities and participation, ranging from global to transnational, national, local, and different combinations thereof, are available to their contemporary successors. Assimilation and transnationalism as coexistent processes Past immigrants' maintenance of diverse transnational connections with people, symbols, and institutions in their countries of origin did not prevent their gradual integration into the host society (see Morawska 2001a for a review of historical studies). Immigration historians have called this process ethnicization, a mixing and blending of old- and new-country identifications and behaviors, depending on the particular circumstances in which this mixing was taking place (see Greene 1975; Sarna 1978; Morawska 1994). ^~ Although it is today more intense and is publicly displayed with much greater ease than in the past, contemporary immigrants' engagement in transnational spaces has not precluded their identification and involvements with the host society. As they are educated in the host society's schools, participate in its popular culture, and enter its workforce, native-born children of immigrants become part of the former while they maintain economic, social, or cultural ties with, and political interests in, their parents' country or region of origin. For contemporary immigrants and ethnics, however, incorporation into the host society has been more varied, twisted and uneven, even within the same immigrant group, than the trajectory prescribed by the conventional assimilation model (which posits the progressive abandonment of old-country ways in favor of the internalization of the dominant mainstream identity and lifestyle of the receiving society). Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 23 (On present-day ethnics' multitrack, "bumpy" assimilation and its "paradoxes," see Gans 1992; Alba 1999; Perlmann and Waldinger 1999). Depending on citizenship and immigration policies of the receiver countries (see Koopmans and Statham in this volume), the economic location of immigrants and their children in the host society, their racial similarity to the members of the dominant group(s), the "fit" of their sociocultural capital with host life orientations and coping strategies, and the scope and intensity of their in-group involvements, three major integration trajectoriescan be distinguished. These trajectories include ^me conventional or upward path into the middle class of the host society; ^downward or segmented (also called oppositional) assimilation into the lower cultural ancf economic segments of the host society; and the ^ethnic or bi-cultural path of integration. (Empirical illustrations of these different paths can be found, e.g., ir^Waters 1999; Jones-Correra 1998; Rumbaut 1994; Laguerre 1998; Mrn'l998~ioV"the United States; and Modood etal. 1998; Migration und Emanzipation 1995; Shadid and Van Koningsveld 1996; Van Hear 1998; Rath etal. 2001 for Europe.) In the first type of incorporation immigrants and their children integrate ■; 4 ',-into the mainstream economy, assimilate the host middle-class's cultural values and lifestyles, develop strong and weak social ties (Granovetter 1973) with the native-born members of the mainstream society, and participate in host political life (citizenship and local involvement). Existing data show steady increases (differently paced for different groups) in host language proficiency, gradual residential ^ispersipn, and naturalization rates among new immigrants, which suggests progress towaTdmthéŕ'thán a retreat from or stalling of incorporation. Certainly, a large proportion of new immigrants' children are still too young to fully assess their progress or decline in mainstream receiver societies. But they have the opportunity, unavailable to past immigrants, for effective public action and protest against barriers to integration, which is carried by contemporary ethnic immigrant organizations and sanctioned by the norm of "just pluralism" in most Western societies. In view of these countervailing circumstances, the proponents of mainstream assimilation, understanding the latter as a multitrack, uneven "general direction toward similarity" (Brubaker in this volume) or as a gradual "convergence around the mean" (Perlmann and Waldinger 1997), argue that not enough time has passed for the eventual pattern to reveal itself - that "the judgment is still out". ^-,. The second type, downward incorporation, applies mostly to lower-class {j? ': immigrants' children who are racially or religiously "othered" by the host society and whose upward mobility is blocked by structural disadvantage 24 Christian Joppke and Ewa fyorawska and racial or religious discrimination by host-country people and í institutions. It implies assimilation into the "adversarial culture" of the 'i underclass based on a willful rejection of mainstream sociocultural ] norms, values, and role models which, in turn, further entraps these 1 people in their circumstances. (See Portes and Zhou 1993 for the paradigmatic statement of the segmented assimilation thesis.) Mexicans in Los Angeles, North African ''beürs" in Trance, or "opt out" groups of young Turkish "denizens" in Germany represent this type of assimilation which incorporates also elements of ethnic adaptation. (See, e.g., Vigil 1988; Leveau 1997; Kastoryano 1996: 133-58, on adversarial cum ethnic assimilation patterns in these three cases.) '"JV%> Tne tnird' ethnic path of integration into the host society involves \ ->' the coexistence or "doubling" (Gans 1997) or fusing into new forms (Foner 1997) of (1) assimilation into common host cultural orientations and behavioral patterns and economic, social and political memberships, and (2) retention or transformation of immigrant traditions and lifestyles, including transnational identities and participation. This pattern of adaptation through íntra-group mixing and blending in different proportions of old- and new-country identificational and behavioral , elements has been called by historians the ethnicization trajectory, and } by immigration sociologists a parallel-path or adhesive assimilation (see, 1 respectively, Sarna 1978; Hurh and Kim 1984). 1 The ethnic trajectory of adaptation has been reported among upwardly mobile immigrants who remain within the boundaries of their ethnic niche in order to better their chances for socioeconomic advancement. It has also appeared as a counter-strategy against downward assimilation whereby, instead of adopting mainstream "underclass" dispositions, immigrants' children retain ethnic identities and social affiliations as a means of individual or group defence against discrimination and rejection by the host society. (On the former, see Morawska's 1990 review of studies in the United States; Body-Gendrot and Martiniello 2000 for Europe; on the latter, see Smith and Guarnizo 1998 for the United States; Vertovec and Rogers 1998 for Europe.) An interesting variety of ethnicization is the development of panethnic identities and organizations, e.g., Asian-American, Hispanic or Latino in the United States, North African in France. Based on shared regional origins, language or religion, such encompassing trans-group identities are usually situationally mobilized for purposes of public protest or political lobbying by immigrant/ethnic groups that consider themselves mistreated by the host society (see Espiritu 1992; Itzigsohn and Dore-Cabral 2000; Vertovec and Rogers 1998 for empirical illustrations of panethnic identities and mobilizations). Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 25 E;ach_of_the_se,difffirent trajectories of integration into the host society can coincide with the maintenance of different forms of identificational and participatory tranjsnjrtton^Hsm. The forms and outcomes of this coexistence depend on specific historical - that is, time- and place-variant -constellations, including the economic and geopolitical positions and interests of sender and receiver countries, their civic-juridical systems and national cultures, and the political, socioeconomic, and racial makeup of particular immigrant groups and their relations with members of the host society. ethnic pattern of adaptation has fused most naturally and most closely with transnational, old^cöüntry involvements of immigrants and their offspringrí?tainstream or upwardjissimilation has coexisted, on the one hand, withlhe symbolic ethnicity~(Gans 1992; WaťersT990)"br the voluntary maintenance by otherwise assimilated individuals of regular, active interests and participation in the country of origin's art, history, cultural customs and events, often combined with repeated visits; on the other hand, it went along with the situational mobilization of sentiments and transnational civic-political involvement in home-country or regional matters (as in the transnational mobilization effects of the Gulf War on the otherwise assimilated middle-class Arab population in France, see Lewis and Schnapper 1994). However, the coexistence of assimilation and sustained transnational identities and participation has often caused tensions in the lives of immigrants and their children. As reported in the United States and in Europe, discomfort has been most common, and most painful, for members of non-white immigrant groups as the result of the contradictory effects of assimilation and racial integration into the host society. For these immigrants and their offspring, integration into the host society entails also loss of the social status associated with non-white racial or non-Western (i.e., Judeo-Christian) religious membership and the blocking rather than opening of advancement opportunities. As Mary Waters observes in the US case, "this turns the basic assumption of the assimilation theories [that host-country identity bestows the higher status] on its head," because acquiring the identity of the receiving society now implies downward mobility (Waters 1999: 93; for a similar situation in Europe see Wrench and Solomos 1993; BaumgartI and Favell 1995). Immigrants and their children from low-status minority groups can cope with this situation in several ways. They can challenge their predicament, / either as an ethnic immigrant.grouper in solidarity with native non-j whites, under the banner of the host nation's ideology of just pluralism \ and equal opportunity for all citizens. They can "retreat" into their/ 26 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska transnational, homebound identities and participation to ease or avert the loss of status and to relieve the traumas of racial prejudice and discrimination experienced in the host society. They can adopt the dominant host society's negative stereotypes of native non-whites as a way to distance themselves from this group. Or, as often happens, they can combine these coping strategies. In either case, the intertwined assimilatory and transnational practices are usually accompanied by feelings of hurt or disappointment. (The above-cited studies of undocumented Mexicans in Los Angeles, North African Moslem "beurs" in France, and young Turkish denizens in Germany document these different strategies; see also Morawska 2001a on the tensions between African Americans and black West Indians in New York, Los Angeles, and Miami; Bonilla etal. 1998 on US Latinos; Chin 1996 on Chinatown gangs.) Immigrant transnationalism and the nation-state The new immigrant transnationalism was originally conceptualized as a strategy of resistance "from below" by members of marginalized and underprivileged racial or ethnic groups from (semi-)peripheral parts of the world against the hegemonic powers of the "core" structures of white receiver societies. Immigrants and their offspring born in these societies escape the latter's control by engaging in transnational spaces, thereby contributing to the general decline of the nation-state's prerogatives to contain and regulate their economic, political, and symbolic activities and commitments. Recently, calls have appeared in the new transnationalism literature to modify this view and to "bring the [sender and receiver] state back in" as an important influence on the ( forms and scope of immigrant transnationalism. (For an overview of | these arguments, see, for example, Geddes and Favell 1999; Faist 2000; | Hollifield 2000). Of concern here, the host nation-state's policies at ' both national and local levels are now being recognized as influencing the intensity, endurance, and, importantly, the consequences of transnational engagements for the integration of immigrants and their children into the receiver society. The receiver states' legal-administrative control of the "belonging and not-belonging" (Barats-Malbrel 1999) of immigrants and their offspring shapes their transnational social and political practices. As Ruud Koopmans and Paul Statham (in this volume) demonstrate, different national I citizenship regimes in Germany, Great Britain, and the Netherlands I differently shape immigrant transnational (homeland-related) politics in the societies of settlement. In particular, the denial of citizenship to immigrants and, in the countries whose citizenship laws and policies Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 27 are informed by jus sanguinis, their native-born children sustains their identification with their home countries and constrains, or channels into an oppositional trajectory, their incorporation into the host society. Conversely, the acceptance or, as is more often the case, tacit tolerance of dual citizenship by the receiver state encourages immigrants or ethnics to engage in bi-national practices, contributing simultaneously to their attachment over time to the host society and to the preservation of transnational commitments. (For empirical illustrations of these effects see, e.g., Hagan 1994 ; Van Hear 1998; Faist 2000; Shain 1999.) Next to political rights, participation in social citizenship or inclusion in the economic and welfare life of the receiver polity matters. In highly regulated welfare states, such as Germany, immigrant groups that do not enjoy füll citizenship are excluded from participation in policy decisions of vital importance to their advancement opportunities, such as job training programs. More market-based welfare states, such as the United States, where paths from school to work are much less regulated by public policies, allow more space for immigrants to incorporate themselves "on their own" by applying their cultural and social capitals. (See Faist 1995 for a comparative analysis of immigrant social citizenship in Germany and the United States.) Receiver states' educational policies influence the form and "contents" of cultural assimilation or ethnicization of immigrants (if they arrive young enough to attend receiver-society schools) and their children. The proportioning and representation of national and multicultural components of school programs regulated by public policies can -contingent on immigrant students' socioeconomic position, political status, and racial membership - either encourage their mainstream symbolic assimilation to the host society or motivate them toward cultural integration along an ethnic or bi-national path. As in the case of social entitlements, the political pressure by immigrant groups on national or, more often, local political institutions on behalf of their interests, can influence the outcomes of these educational policies. (See, for example, Bleich 1999 and Tyack, forthcoming, for illustrations of these effects in Europe and the United States, respectively.) Not only domestic but also foreign policies of the receiver state influence immigrants' or ethnics' transnational involvements. The host state's geopolitical interests have incited or discouraged sustained transnational engagements of some immigrant groups and, thus, legitimized or stigmatized the ethnic or bi-national path of assimilation among their members. For example, because of the US government's foreign policy interests during the prolonged Cold War with the Soviet Union and, 28 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska specifically, its attempts to weaken the latter on its own territory, it overtly encouraged transnational political lobbying by East European ethnic leaders and organizations to pressure communist governments on human rights issues and persecuted groups or individuals, to broadcast uncensored information and anti-Soviet propaganda into Eastern Europe, to solicit material help for dissident groups, and so on. The Cuban refugee community in Miami received support from the US government for its transnational anti-communist propaganda in Cuba, and the former also received significant assistance by the Cuban Refugee Program and other federal initiatives to facilitate the adaptation of Cuban emigres in the United States. (On "transnational politics" of East European and Cuban Americans and its support by the US government see, e.g., Jacobson 1995; Cohen 1997; Shain 1999; Portes and Stepick 1993.) In comparison, the transnational engagement by Arab Americans in Middle Eastern politics on behalf of Arab interests has met a very different response from the US government. The Middle Eastern conflict and, in particular, the Palestinian intifada in Israeli-occupied territories reinforced , panethnic solidarity and mobilized politically a highly diverse and í contentious community of Arab Americans. A significant part of this [ community articulates its support for the.Palestinian cause in "assimila-\ tory" terms of American values of human rights, freedom, and 1 self-determination. Even though the Palestinian is thus presented as the patriotic American cause, because of its foreign policy commitments in the Middle East the US government has discouraged, if not stigmatized, this transnational commitment of Arab Americans. As a result, despite the official ideology of pluralism and tolerance for transnational involvements in the United States, American Arabs' bi- or pan-national commitments have come to resemble the old type of closet transnationalism of earlier immigrants. (For Arab American transnational politics and resulting tensions with US foreign policy interests, see Shain 1999.) Another configuration of receiver state policies, transnationalism and integration characterizes the case of Haitian immigrants in America (see Vickerman 1999; Stepick 1996; Shain 1999). The Haitian American community's transnational engagement in 1980-81 on behalf of deposed President Aristide's democratic opposition in Haiti and for the admission of the Haitian boat refugees who had been isolated in camps and threatened with deportation was snubbed by the US government, which viewed Aristide and his supporters as too radical for its foreign-policy interests in the region. The support offered by the African-American leadership (the NAACP), whose political lobbying under the banner of racial solidarity eventually moved the US government to admit the Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 29 Haitian refugees, had the effect of enhancing Haitian immigrants' political association with American black society. It did not eliminate, however, the earlier noted status-distancing by Haitian immigrants from native blacks. The political solidarity of native blacks with Haitian immigrants, combined with the latter's distance to African Americans in terms of home-country identities and cultural superiority, has yielded among Haitians a unique blend of transnationalism and incorporation, which is different from that of American Arabs. Overview of the book The first part of this book deals with liberal immigrant-receiving states' renewed emphasis on citizenship and assimilation, the second with immigrants' straddling between assimilation and transnationalism. Rogers Brubaker opens the first part with a provocative survey of the "return of assimilation" in France, Germany, and the United States. This is no simple return to the nationalizing state of the past, because "assimilation" has taken on novel features - from cultural to structural, \ s from organic to abstract, from transitive to intransitlveľ Han Entzinger \ -discusses why one of Europe's paragons of multiculturalism policies, the Netherlands, has recently turned its back on them. In a comparison of recent nationality reforms and debates in Europe, Randall Hansen shows that immigrant integration remains both nationally bounded and dependent upon national citizenship. Alex Aleinikoff makes a similar argument regarding the United States, where the "postnational perspective" fails to give an accurate depiction of US models of rights and membership. The recognition of rights for non-nationals in the US is not based on "global" norms transcending the nation-state, but is a core attribute of American constitutionalism since the founding period. Ewa Morawska begins the second part of the book with a comparative discussion of the different constellations of transnationalism and assimilation among immigrants and their children in the United States, mapping the different circumstances that generate these varieties, and proposing a three-step research strategy to account for the simultaneity of assimilation and transnationalism. In her multicase study of immigrant communities in Boston, Peggy Levitt demonstrates that increasing numbers of immigrants "keep feet in two worlds," but the particular forms of their integration into American society and of their transnational engagements vary with the institutional arenas of immigrants' participation and with their class and life-stage positions. Turning to three European cases (Britain, the Netherlands, and Gennany), 30 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska Ruud Koopmans and Paul Statham show that national citizenship regimes, instead of being devalued or bypassed by transnationalism, have actually shaped the way transnational migrant claims are expressed. Their data reveal that transnational ("homeland") claims are strongest in the (until recently) most exclusive citizenship regime, Germany's. This suggests that, as citizenship regimes in liberal states (including Germany) are becoming more inclusive, transnational claims-making might become "less rather than more frequent... in the years to come." Notes 1 Access to many of these programs has subsequently been restored (see Freeman 2001). 2 See the good critique of the premises of "normative consensus" and "state-centrism" underlying the notion of immigrant integration by Phalet (2000). 3 The concept of "integration", of course, has deep roots in the classical sociology from Durkheim to Parsons, which sought to provide answers to the question, "How is social order possible?" However, as such it remained territorially anonymous. In its territorial (or "national") specificity, the notion of (immigrant) integration is a practical category, originating in the political sphere. 4 Even in France, the notion of assimilation has officially been discarded (see Haut Conseil ä ľíntégration 1993). But see its academic resurrection by Tribalat (1995), and the discussion by Brubaker (this volume). 5 Examples are Schnapper (1992), or Todd (1994). The most sophisticated versions are Soysal (1994: ch. 3) and Favell (1997). 6 Interestingly, and misleadingly, the Haut Conseil couched its nominal joining of the liberal mainstream in an anachronistic persistence of "national models," distinguishing the French "logique ďéqualité" from the "logique des minorités" allegedly in force in Britain and the Netherlands (Haut Conseil 1993:35f). For the obsolescence of the "minority" approach in the Netherlands, see Entzinger's chapter in this volume. 7 This critique of the "national model" notion is not to deny significant institutional variations of integrating immigrants across states, which reflect historically particular state- and nation-building experiences (on this, and their impact on migrants' "claims-making", see Koopmans and Statham in this volume). However, these persistent institutional differences are to be distinguished from explicit "philosophies" of integration, which - to the limited degree that they exist at all- are increasingly converging across liberal states (or so is our claim). 8 Our notion of de-etbnicized citizenship (see below) presumes the weakening of nati on-building pretensions in contemporary liberal states. 9 This difference is of course nil to the degree that Canada and Australia are nations of immigrants. 10 In 1996, 30.6 percent of non-Nordic citizens were unemployed (as against 7.3 percent unemployment among Swedes) (Soininen 1999: 694). Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 31 11 The Dutch model of mandatory integration courses for newcomers is about to be adopted in Germany as well (Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, 10 May 2001, p. 4). 12 For Europe, see Soysal (1994); extending this argument to the United States, Jacobson (1996: ch. 5). 13 Yet see note 1. 14 The "covenant" idea is also invoked in the 1997 final report of the US Commission for Immigration Reform: "[T]he ideal of a covenant between immigrant and nation still captures the essence of Americanization" (p. 27). 15 An exception is the United Kingdom, with its common-law based jus soli regime, and former colonial powers (such as, in addition to the UK, France and the Netherlands), with their inclusive and preferential citizenship schemes for the members of their former colonies. 16 Italy's left-wing government under G. Amato announced a similar reform in December 2000, with the promise of delivering before the next national elections in May 2001 ("Piu facile diventare italiani," la Repubblica, 22 December 2000, p. 1); predictably, the reform was never heard of since, presumably becoming stalled in Italy's byzantinic political process. 17 "Sprachtests erschweren die Einbürgerung," Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitimg, 31 December 1999, p. 3. 18 Even the conservative opposition party (CDU), which in the course of Germany's current reopening toward new labor migration loudly propagated the existence of a German Leitkultur that immigrants would have to adjust to, has in the meantime dropped this contested notion (CDU 2001). References Alba, Richard (1999). "Immigration and the American Realities of Assimilation and Multiculturalism," Sociological Forum, 14(1): 3-25. Albers, Hartmut (1994). "Glaubensfreiheit und schulische Integration von Ausländerkindern," Deutsches Verwaltungsbtatt, 1 September: 984-90. Amersfoort, Hans van (1999). "Migration Control and Minority Policy: The Case OflHěT^efHéllands/' in: Grete Brochmann and Tomas Hammar, eds. Mechanisms of Immigration Control. Oxford: Berg. Bade, Klaus (1984). Auswanderer, Wanderarbeiter, Gastarbeiter. Ostfildern: Scripta Mercaturae. Barats-Malbrel, Christine (1999). "The Politicization of Belonging: Post-war Legal Developments in the Administrative Identitites of Non-nationals in France," in Geddes and Favell (2000). Basch, Linda, Nina Glick Schiller and Cristina Szanton Blanc (1994). Nations Unbound. Langhorne, Pa: Gordon and Breach. Bauböck, Rainer (1999). Cultural Minority Rights in Public Education. Unpublished manuscript. Baumgartl, Bernd and Adrian Favell, eds. (1995). New Xenophobia in Europe. The Hague: Kluwer Law International. Beck, Ulrich (1986). Risikogesellschaft. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Bellah, Robert etal. (1985). Habits of the Heart. Berkeley: University of California Press. Bleich, Erik (1999). "Re-imagined Communities? Education Policies and National Belonging in Britain and France," in Andrew Geddes and Adrian Favell, eds. The Politics of Belonging. Aldershot: Ashgate, 60-75. 32 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska Body-Gendrot, Sophie and Marco Maitinieilo, eds. (2000). Minorities in European Cities. London: Macmillan - now Palgrave Macmillan. Bommes, Michael (1999). Migration und nationaler Wohlfahitsstaat. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag. Bonilla, Frank etal., eds. (1998). Borderless Latinos, Latin Americans, and the Paradox of Interdependence. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Bourdieu, Pierre (1989). La noblesse d'etat Paris: Minuit. Brubaker, Rogers (1992). Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. ---------(1996). Nationalism Rep-anted. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Carens, Joseph (2000). Culture, Citizenship, and Community. Oxford: Oxford University Press. CDU (Christlich Demokratische Union Deutschlands) (2001). Zuwanderung steuern. Integration fördern. Berlin (hectographed). Chin, Ko-Hn (1996). Chinatown Gangs: Extortion, Enterprise, and Ethnicity. New York: Oxford University Press. Cohen, Robin (1997). "Diasporas, the Nation-State, and Globalisation," in Wang Gungwu, ed., Global History and Migrations. Boulder, Co: Westview Press, 117-44. Coleman, Jules and Sarah Harding (1995). "Citizenship, the Demands of Justice, and the Moral Relevance of Political Borders," in: Warren Schwartz, Justice in Immigration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Crowley, John and Patrick Weil (1994). "integration in Theory and Practice," West European Politics 17(2): 110-26. Deutsch, Karl W. etal. (1957). Political Community in the North Atlantic Area, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Entzinger, Han (1998). "Zu einem Modell der Inkorporation von Einwanderern: das Beispiel der Niederlande," in: Michael Bommes and Jost Halfmann, eds. Migration in nationalen Wohlfahrtsstaaten. Osnabrück: Universitätsverlag Rasch. ---------(2000). Towards a Model oflncofpomtion: The Case of the Netherlands. Unpublished manuscript. Espiritu, Yen Le (1992). Asian American Panethnidty. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Faist, Thomas (1995). Social Citizenship for Whom? Aldershot: Ashgate. ---------(1998). "Transnational Social Spaces Out of International Migration: Evolution, Significance, and future Prospects," Archives Europécnnes de Sociologie, 30(2): 213-47. Faist, Thomas (2000). The Volume and Dynamics of International Migration and Transnational Social Spaces. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Fassin, Eric (1999). "'Good to Think'", in: C.Joppke and S.Lukes, Multicultural Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Favell, Adrian (1998). Philosophies of Integration. Basingstoke: Macmillan - now Palgrave Macmillan. --------- (2000). "Integration Policy and Integration Research," in: A.Aleinikoff and D.Kfusmeyer, Citizenship Today. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press. Federal Commissioner for Foreigner Affairs (2000). Vierter Bericht zur Lage der Ausländer in der Bundesrepublik Deutschland. Berlin: Government Printing Office, Foner, Nancy (1997). "What's New About TransnationaJism? New York Immigrants Today and at the Turn of the Century," Diaspora, 6(3): 355-75. Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 33 Freeman, Gary (2001). "Client Politics or Populism? Immigration Reform in the United States," in: V.Guiraudon and C.Joppke, eds. Controlling a New Migration World. London: Routledge. Gans, Herbert (1992). "Second Generation Decline: Scenarios for the Economic and Ethnic Futures of Post-1965 American Immigrants," Ethnic and Racial Studies, 15(2): 173-92. --------- (1997). "Toward a Reconciliation of 'Assimilation' and 'Pluralism': The Interplay of Acculturation and Ethnic Retention," International Migration Review, 31(4): 875-93. Geddes, Andrew and Adrian Favell, eds. (1999). The Politics of Belonging: Migrants and Minorities in Contemporary Europe. Aldershot: Ashgate. Gerstle, Gary (1997). "Liberty, Coercion, and the Making of Americans," Journal of American History, September: 525-58. Glick Schiller, Nina and Georges Fouron (1998). "Transnational Lives and National Identities: The Identity Politics of Haitian Immigrants." in Michael Smith and Luis Guarnizo, eds. Transnationalism from Below. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 130-64. Granovetter, Mark (1973). "The Strength of Weak Ties," American Journal of Sociology, 78(1), 1360-88. Greene, Victor (1975). For God and Country. Madison: State Historical Society of Wisconsin. Guttierez, David (1997). "Transnationalism and Ethnic Politics in the United States: Reflections on Recent History," paper presented at a conference on Immigrants, Civic Culture, and Modes of Political Incorporation, Social Science Research Council, Santa Fe, May 2-4. Hagan, J.M. (1994). Deciding to be Legal: A Maya Community in Houston. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Hansen, Randall (1998). "A European Citizenship or a Europe of Citizens," Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies, 24: 751-68. Hansen, Randall and Patrick Weil, eds. (2001). Towards a European Nationality: Citizenship, Immigration and Nationality Law in the European Union. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Haut Conseil ä ľintégration (1993). Ľintégration ä la francaise. Paris: La documentation francaise. Higham, John (1955). Strangers in the Land. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press. Hirschman, Charles, Philip Kasinitz and Josh DeWind, eds. (1999). The Handbook of International Migration: The American Experience. New York: Russell Sage. Hollifield, James (2000). "The Politics of International Migration: How Can We 'Bring the State Back In'?" in Caroline Brettel and James Hollifield, eds. Migration Theory: Talking Across Disciplines. New York: Routledge. Hurh, Won Moo and Kwang Chung Kim (1984). Korean Immigrants in North America. Madison, NJ: Farleigh Dickinson University Press. Itzigsohn, Jose and Carlos Dore-Cabral (2000). "Competing Identities? Race, Ethinicity and Panethincity Among Dominicans in the United States," Sociological Forum, 1S(2): 225-47. Jackson Preece, Jennifer (1998). National Minorities in the European Nation-States System. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Jacobson, David (1996). Rights Across Borders. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press. 34 Christian foppke and Ewa Morawska Jacobson, Matthew Frye (1995). Special Sorrows: The Diasporic Imagination of Irish, Polish, and Jewish Immigrants in the United States. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Jones-Correra, Michael (1998). Between Two Nations: The Political Predicament of Latinos in New York. Itacha, NY: Cornell University Press. Joppke, Christian (1998). "Immigration Challenges the Nation-State," in: C. Joppke, Challenge to the Nation-State. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ---------(1999). Immigration and the Nation-State: The United States, Germany, and Great Britain. Oxford: Oxford University Press. --------- (2000). "Mobilization of Culture and the Reform of Citizenship Law: Germany and the United States," in: R. Koopmans and P. Statham eds., Challenging Immigration and Ethnic Relations Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. --------- (2002). "Sovereignty and Citizenship in a World of Migration," in: M, Likosky, ed. Transnational Legal Processes. London: Butterworths. Kastoryano, Riva (1996). La France, ľ Altemagne et leurš immigrés. Paris: Armand Colin. Kilic, Memet (1994). Deutsch-Türkische DoppelstaatsangehÖrigkeit?" Das Standesamt, 48: 73-78. Koslowski, Rey (2000), Migrant? and Citizens. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Kymlicka, Will (1995). Multicultural Citizenship. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ---------(1998). Finding Our Way. Toronto: Oxford University Press. Laguerre, Michel (1998). Diasporic Citizenship: Haitian Americans in Transnational America. New York: St Martin's Press - now Palgrave Macmillan, Leveau, Remy (1997). "The Political Culture of the 'Beurs'/' in Steven Vertovec and Ceri Peach eds. Islam in Europe: The Politics of Religion and Community, New York: St Martin's Press - now Palgrave Macmiflan 147-55. Lewis, Bernard and Dominique Schnapper, eds. (1994). Muslims in Europe. London: St Martin's Press - now Palgrave Macmillan. Lie, John (1995). "International Migration to Transnational Diaspora," Contemporary Sociology, 24: 303-306. Lijphart, Arend (1968). The Politics of Accommodation. Berkeley: University of California Press. Luhmann, Niklas (1986). Ökologische Kommunikation. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag. ---------(1997). Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft (two volumes). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Migration und Emanzipazion. Türkische Frauen in Nordrhein-Westfalen (1995). Zentrum für Turkeistudien (HRSG.) Opladen: Leske & Budrich. Min, Pyong Gap (1998). Changes and Conflicts: Korean Immigrant Families in New York. Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon. Modood, Tariq etal. (1998). Ethnic Minorities in Britain. London: Policy Studies Institute. Morawska, Ewa (1994). "In Defense of the Assimilation Model," Journal of American Ethnic History, Winter: 76-87. ---------(1990). "The Sociology and Historiography of Immigration," in: V. Yans- McLaughlin, ed. Immigration Reconsidered. New York: Oxford University Press. ---------(2001a). "Immigrants, Transnationalism, and Ethnicization," in: Gary Gerstle and John Mollenkopf, eds. E Pluribus Unum? Contemporary and Historical Perspectives on Immigrant Political Incorporation. New York: Russell Sage. Integrating Immigrants in Liberal Nation-States 35 ---------(2001b). "Immigrant-Black Dissensions in American Cities: An Argument for Multiple Explanations," in: Douglas Massey and Elijah Anderson eds. Problem of the Century: Racial Stratification in the United States at Century's End, New York: Russell Sage. Ogburn, William (1957). "Cultural Lag as Theory," in: W. Ogburn, On Culture and Social Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964. Pedraza, Silvia (1996). "Cuba's Refugees: Manifold Migrations," in: Silvia Pedraza and Ruben Rumbaut eds. Origins and Destinies: Immigration, Race, and Ethnicity in America, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 263-79. Perlmann, Joel and Roger Waldinger (1997). "Second-Generation Decline" International Migration Review, 31(4): 893-923. Perry, Stephen (1995). "Immigration, Justice, and Culture," in: Warren Schwartz, Justice in Immigration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Phalet, Karen (2000), Beyond National Integration Paradigms. Paper presented at ~tnT2l)TjOConference of the Council of European Studies, April 1-3, Chicago. Pickus, Noah, ed. (1998). Immigration and Citizenship in the 21st Century. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. Portes, Alejandro (1997). "Immigration Theory for a New Century: Some Problems and Opportunities," International Migration Review, 31(4): 799-825. Portes, Alejandro and Alex Stepick (1993). City on Edge: The Transformation of Miami. Berkeley: University of California Press. Portes, Alejandro and Min Zhou (1993). "The New Second Generation: Segmented Assimilation and its Variants," Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Sciences, 530: 74-96. Rath, Jan etal. (2001). Western Europe and its Islam. Leiden: Brill Academic Publishers. Rumbaut, Ruben (1994). "The Crucible Within: Ethnic Identity, Self-Esteem, and Segmented Assimilation among Children of Immigrants," International Migration Review, Winter: 748-94. Sarna, Jonathan (1978). "From Immigrants to Ethnics: Toward a New Theory of Ethnicization," Ethnicity, 5, December: 73-78. Schain, Martin (1999). "Minorities and Immigrant Incorporation in France," in: C. Joppke and S. Lukes eds., Multicultural Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schnapper, Dominique (1992). L'Europe des immigrés. Paris: Editions Francois Bourin. Shadid, W.A.li, and P.S. Van Koningsveld, eds. (1996). Political Participation and Identities of Muslims in Non-Muslim States. Kampen: Kok Pharos Publishing House. Shain, Yossi (1999). Marketing the American Creed Abroad: Diasporas in the US and Their Homelands. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Smith, Peter and Eduardo Guarnizo, eds. (1998). Transnationalism from Below. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Soininen, Maritta (1999). "The 'Swedish model' as an Institutional Framework for Immigrant Membership Rights," Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies, 25(4): 685-702. Soysal, Yasemin (1994). Limits to Citizenship. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Stepick, Alex (1996). "Pride, Prejudice, and Poverty: Economic, Social, Political, and Cultural Capital among Haitians in Miami," in Harriet Duleep and Phanindra 36 Christian Joppke and Ewa Morawska Wunnava Orcutt, eds. Immigrants and Immigration Policy: Individual Skills, Family Ties, and Group Identities. Greenwich, CN: JAI Press, 133-48. Todd, Emmanuel (1994). Le destin des immigrés. Paris: Seuil. Tribalat, Michele (1995). Faire France. Paris: La Découverte. US Commission on Immigration Reform (1997). Becoming an American. Washington, DC: Government Printing Office. Tyack, Edward (Forthcoming). "School for Citizens: The Politics of Civic Education," in Gary Gerstle and John Mollenkopf, eds., Immigrants, Civic Culture, and Modes of Political Incorporation, New York: Russell Sage. Van Hear, Nicholas (1998). New Diasporas: The Mass Exodus, Dispersal and Regrouping of Migrant Communities. Seattle, WA: University of Washington Press. Vertovec, Steven and Robin Cohen, eds. (1999). Migration, Diasporas, and Transnationalism. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing Co. Vertovec, Steven and Ceri Peach, eds. (1997). Islam in Europe: The Politics of Religion and Community. London: Macmillan - now Palgrave Macmillan. Vertovec, Steven and Alisdair Rogers, eds. (1998). Muslim European Youth: Reproducing Ethnicity, Religion, and Culture. Aldershot: Ashgate. Vickerman, Milton (1999). Crosscurrents: West Indian Immigrants and Race. New York: Oxford University Press. Vigil, James Diego (1988). Barrio Gangs: Street Life and Identity in Southern California. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. Waters, Mary (1990). Ethnic Options: Choosing Identities in America. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. ---------(1999). Black Identities. West Indian Immigrant Dreams and American Realities. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Wrench, John and John Solomos, eds. (1993). Racism and Migration in Western Europe. Oxford: Berg. Wyman, Joseph (1993). Round-Trip to America: The Immigrants Return to Europe, 1880-1930. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Zappala, Gianni, and Stephen Castles (2000). "Citizenship and Immigration in Australia," in: T.A. Aleinikoff and D. Klusmeyer, eds. From Migrants to Citizens. Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Zolberg, Aristide and Long Litt Woon (1999). "Why Islam is Like Spanish," Politics and Society 27(1): 5-38. Parti Changing State Policies 2 The Return of Assimilation? Changing Perspectives on Immigration and its Sequels in France, Germany, and the United States Rogers Brubaker The differentialist turn "The point about the melting pot," wrote Nathan Glazer and Daniel Patrick Moynihan in the preface to their influential Beyond the Melting Pot, "is that it did not happen." This "failure to melt" thesis was iconoclastic when the book was published in 1963. But it had become widely accepted already by the end of the decade - well before the post-1965 revival of mass immigration began to transform the American urban landscape. By the 1980s, when the effects of the "new 'new immigration'" had become unmistakable, earlier conceptions of assimilation seemed to many to have lost all relevance. When Glazer published We Are All Multiculturalists Now in 1997, he was writing as eminence grise, not as iconoclastic intellectual.1 Pluralistic understandings of persisting diversity, once a challenge to the conventional wisdom, had become the conventional wisdom, not only in the US and other classic countries of immigration such as Canada and Australia, but also in much of northern and western Europe. There is obviously a good deal of truth to this conventional wisdom. Public discourse and public policies bearing on the integration of immigrants are indeed vastly more "differentialist" - vastly more sensitive to and supportive of "difference" - today than they were, say, in the period between the two world wars in France or the US, or in the early postwar decades in the US. The 1980s and 90s indeed witnessed an 39 40 Rogers Brubaker unprecedented efflorescence of differentialist discourse - and differentialist integration policies - in all Western countries of immigration. This differentialist turn has not been restricted to, or even centered on, the immigration issue. Especially in the US, but in a more limited sense in Western Europe as well, it has been a much broader and more general movement or thought and opinion. It has found expression in movements to preserve or strengthen regional languages and cultures in Europe (Keating 1996); in demands for, and greater recognition of, the autonomy of indigenous peoples in the US, Canada, Australia, Russia, Latin America, and elsewhere (Brasted era/. 1985; Kymlicka 1995); in Black Power, Afrocentrist, and other anti-assimilationist movements involving African-Americans (Howe 1998); in the shift from an individualist, opportunity-oriented, and color-blind to a collectivist, results-oriented, and color-conscious interpretation of civil rights legislation in the US (Glazer 1978); in multicuituralist revisions of school and university curricula (Nash etat 1997; Glazer 1997); in gynocentric or "difference" feminism (Irigaray 1993); in gay pride and other movements based on the public affirmation of alternative sexualities (Johnston 1973); in claims by other putative cultural communities - including, for example, the deaf (Lane 1992) - for autonomy; in generalized opposition to the homogenizing, centralizing claims of the modern nation-state; in anti-foundationalist understandings of the production of knowledge in bounded, historically and socially situated epistemic communities (Hollinger 1997); in other poststructuralist and postmodernist critiques of the allegedly falsely universal premises of Enlightenment thought; and in the shift from an understanding of politics emphasizing the pursuit of putatively universal interests to one emphasizing the recognition of avowedly particularist identities (Young 1990). Today, however, this massive differentialist turn in social thought, public discourse, and public policy shows signs of having exhausted itself. Differentialist stances have long been a lightning rod for criticism from cultural conservatives (D'Souza 1991) and from the economistic, resolutely anti-identitarian left, in recent years, though, criticism has come increasingly "from within," that is, from the "cultural left" itself, from persons sympathetic to the claims of cultural difference, yet uncomfortable with their absolutization (Hollinger 1995; Gitlin 1995; Brubaker and Cooper 2000). Opposition to the relativistic, indeed ultimately solipsistic implications of epistemological insiderism; concern over the fragmenting, in certain respects disabling consequences of identity politics; resurgent interest in forms of civic commonality; rethinking of the modalities of and rationale for affirmative action, not The Return of Assimilation? 41 only on the part of its longstanding critics on the right, but on the part of its longstanding defenders on the left - these and other developments suggest that, in some respects at least, the maximally differential ist moment may have passed. In the domain of immigration, too, there are signs that the differentialist tide may have begun to ebb. Instead of a definitive, unidirectional shift from assimilation to multiculturalism, we have begun to see a shift in the opposite direction. To call this the "return of assimilation" is undoubtedly too grand a label for the relatively modest and uneven shift I will describe; hence the question mark in my title. But it may usefully caution us against overhastily consigning assimilation to the dustbin of history. Two meanings of "assimilation" What do I mean by the "return of assimilation"? I do not mean a return to the normative expectations, analytical models, public policies, or informal practices associated with the ideal of Anglo-conformity or the increasingly nativist Americanization movement after World War I (Gleason 1980); or to those associated with the schoolteachers of the French Third Republic, notorious for shaming and humiliating those who spoke languages or dialects other than standard French (Weber 1976: 313); or to those associated with the harsh Imperial German effort to "Germanize" its largely Polish-speaking eastern borderlands (Broszat 1972: 129-72);2 or to any of the many other lamentable instances of harshly homogenizing state projects. This should go without saying, but assimilation has acquired such a bad name in many American differentialist circles that it has come to be associated, as a kind of automatic reflex, with the narrowest understanding of Anglo-conformity or the worst excesses of Americanization campaigns. In Germany, if anything, the word "assimilation" has been even more strongly "contaminated" and disqualified by its association with forcible Germanization. In France, by contrast, the word itself was never so thoroughly discredited. But in France, too, it was tainted by association with the sometimes brutally homogenizing aspirations and practices of Jacobin Republicanism. So what are we talking about when we talk about "assimilation"? What is it that is "returning," if it is not these normattvely and analytically discredited models? To address this question, we must distinguish between two basic meanings of "assimilation." One is general and abstract; the other is specific and organic. The two meanings are related, 42 Rogers Brubaker but they differ sharply in their affective overtones, moral and political connotations, and intellectual respectability. In the general and abstract sense, the core meaning is increasing similarity or likeness. Not identity, but similarity. To assimilate means to become similar (when the word is used /«transitively) or to make similar or treat as similar (when it is used transitively). Assimilation is thus the process of becoming similar, or of making similar or treating as similar. In the specific and organic sense, the root meaning is transitive. To assimilate something is to "convert [it] into a substance of its own nature, as the bodily organs convert food into blood, and thence into animal tissue... to absorb into the system, [to] incorporate" (Oxford English Dictionary). Assimilation in this sense implies complete absorption. In the general, abstract sense, the accent is on the process, not on some final state, and assimilation is a matter of degree. Assimilation designates a direction of change, not a particular degree of similarity. In the specific, organic sense, by contrast, the accent is on the end state, and assimilation is a matter of either/or, not of degree. It is the connotations chiefly of this organic meaning, with its biological metaphor of incorporation, that have discredited the term, making it seem normatively retrograde (given our contemporary appreciation of "difference" and diversity), analytically disreputable (given its superannuated organismic understanding of society), and empirically wrong (with its implication of complete absorption). In addition, one aspect of the general, abstract meaning has stood out as normatively and analytically problematic. This is the transitive use of "assimilate" to mean "make similar," which suggests state policies and programs of "forced assimilation," or at least policies and programs that seek to assimilate people against their will. Such policies and programs have rightly come to be seen as morally and politically repugnant. Abundant historical and comparative evidence, moreover, suggests that they rarely work, and that they are indeed more likely to strengthen than to erode differences, by provoking a reactive mobilization against such assimilatory pressures. Analytically, we may have good reason to speak of assimilationist policies; but such policies need not have assimilationist outcomes.3 Yet when used intransitively in the general, abstract sense of becoming similar - becoming similar in certain respects, which obviously have to be specified - assimilation does not seem to be morally objectionable, analytically useless, or empirically wrong as a conceptual instrument for studying populations of immigrant origin. Indeed the use of some The Return of Assimilation? 43 such notion - if only to pose certain questions about patterns of "integration," "adaptation," or "incorporation," terms that have been preferred to "assimilation" in many recent discussions4 - would seem to be analytically indispensable. I return to this point in the conclusion. Here I simply wish to underscore that it is this intransitive understanding of "assimilation," this normative and analytical concern with the nature and extent of emerging similarities in particular domains between populations of immigration origin and "host" populations, that I see "returning" in recent years. Three cases The trend that concerns me has been much stronger in France than in Germany, with the US somewhere in between. This might lead one to think that the "return of assimilation" is simply an artefact of the cases I have chosen, which include the US, historically the paradigmatic country of immigrant assimilation, and France, the European country with the longest, strongest, and most ideologically elaborated tradition of assimilation. There is something to this: had I chosen different cases -for example the UK, Sweden, the Netherlands, and Germany - the trend would have been less clear-cut. Yet the trend cannot be dismissed out of hand as an artefact of the cases selected for discussion here. In the first place, the return of assimilation in France and the US involves a marked return, not simply the persistence of something always present. I want to stress this reactive moment of return, and to situate it in the context of a preceding "differentialist" turn in both France and the US. Moreover, there has been a modest assimilationist turn not only in Germany (which I discuss below) but also in the Netherlands (Koopmans and Statham 2000; Thränhardt 2000) and Sweden (Soininen 1999: 689-91), two other countries with relatively "differentialist" incorporation regimes. Over the longer term, as a third generation of immigrant origin emerges, it is likely that a concern with at least some dimensions of assimilation will become increasingly salient throughout Europe. I obviously cannot give here a comprehensive account of processes of -or ideas about - immigrant integration in France, Germany, and the US, let alone the other countries I have mentioned. Instead, I will briefly sketch three illustrative vignettes, drawn from different countries and from different domains. I discuss the return of assimilation in public discourse in France, in public policy in Germany, and in scholarly research in the US. 44 Rogers Bnibaker France: From droit ä la difference to droit ä la resemblance One might think there was not much of a story to be told about France. Why talk of a return of assimilation in a country that has long been the paradigmatic exemplar of assimilation, transforming peasants - and immigrants - into Frenchmen, in what Gérard Noirieí has called le creuset francais, the French melting pot (Weber 1976, Noiriel 1988)? But to frame the issue in this way - to focus only on the Jacobin-Republican assimilationist tradition, or assimilationist myth - is to forget the strong differentialist turn that occurred in French public discussion of immigration and other issues in the 1970s and early 1980s, precisely in reaction against the Jacobin and assimilationist tradition. Indeed differentialist discourse received one of its sharpest and most lapidary - if ambiguous -formulations in the characteristic French slogan of those years: the droit ä la difference. True, the differentialist turn was much stronger in rhetoric than in reality: differentialism remained largely symbolic {Schnapper 1992: 119) and was embedded only relatively weakly in policies and institutionalized practices - for example, in the program in which foreign instructors, selected and paid by foreign governments as a result of bilateral agreements concluded with the French state, were recruited to offer instruction in so-called "languages and cultures of origin" in French public schools, indeed during regular school hours (Boyzon-Fradet 1992: 155ff).s But at the level of public discussion, differentialism was clearly ascendant, indeed triumphant during the early years of the Socialist government in France in the early 1980s.fi It is important to note that differentialism was gaining ground on the French right as well as the left. The historian and philosopher Pierre-André Taguieff has analyzed the rise of a differentialist - one could even say multiculturalist - "new right" in France in the 1970s and 1980s, clustered around the enigmatic figure of Alain de Benoist. No longer xenophobic but formally "heterophile," anti-racist, and egalitarian, the new differentialists of the right emphasized, indeed absolutized, cultural difference, seeking to "preserve at any price collective identities, and thus differences between communities, haunted by the danger of their destruction through mixing, physical and cultural" (Taguieff 1994: 66-67). What happened to the ascendant differentialism? In two words: Le Pen. Although Le Pen and the intellectuals associated with him actually belonged to a different segment of the right than the small circle of principled differentialists analyzed by Taguieff, they too adopted a differentialist idiom, adroitly turning it to their own purposes. Droit ä la The Return of Assimilation? 45 difference? Mais oui, Men sůr, chez vous. But here, in France - so went the argument - it's we, the "real" French, who have our own right to be different, our own right to preserve our own "identity" from unwanted admixture. As a result, the moral and political ambiguity, and the exclusionary potential, of culturalist differentialism were brought into sharp focus -indeed much sharper focus in France than elsewhere. It was this political and ideological conjuncture that set the stage for the return of assimilation. The much-vaunted slogan of the droit ä la difference disappeared with astonishing rapidity. By the late 1980s, it was scarcely to be heard. One was more likely to hear of the droit ä la resemblance, to which Harlem Désir himself appealed in a widely watched TV appearance in 1987 - or of the droit ä ľindifférence, in effect the right to be treated like everyone else. In the wake of the differentialist collapse, there was a resurgence of neo-republican, neo-universalist, and at least hesitatingly neo-assimilationist discourse, elaborated by such public intellectuals as Alain Finkielkraut (1987), Taguieff (1996), and especially Emmanuel Todd (1994). Their views do not go unchallenged, of course; there are sophisticated voices such as Michel Wieviorka (1996) who continue to defend a moderately differentialist position; but on the whole, the sudden and virtually complete collapse of simplistic, sloganeering differentialism and the equally sudden resurgence of universalist, assimilationist discourse about immigration is striking. Certainly, no equally sharp shift in the center of gravity of public discourse has occurred elsewhere. Germany: Rethinking institutionalized separateness While my French vignette concerned public discourse, my German story is about public policy. German policy vis-ä-vis immigrants and their descendants has been strongly differentialist - much more so than French policy even during the years of ascendant differentialist rhetoric in France.7 Consider three indicators of differentialist policy in Germany. First, instruction in languages and cultures of origin has been much more widespread in Germany than in France, and indeed has been part of the obligatory curriculum in some Länder (Castles etah 1984: 175). (Since education is the responsibility of the individual Lander, this has varied a good deal from state to state; Bavaria, in particular, was long notorious for educating foreigners in segregated, homeland-oriented classes.) Second, there is the peculiar German system of social service provision to populations of immigrant origin. Responsibility for such provision 46 Rogers Brubaker was farmed out by the state to the three major nonstate charitable organizations - one affiliated with the Catholic Church, a second with the Evangelical Church, the third with the Social Democratic Party. Jurisdiction was apportioned in such a way that foreigners were allocated to a particular charitable organization on the basis of their national origin, so that all Turks were the responsibility of one organization, all Italians of a second, and so on. As critics have observed (Puskeppeleit and Thränhardt 1990; cf. Älund and Schierup 1991 on the somewhat similar Swedish case), this system not only treats immigrants as passive clients of the charitable organizations, but also tends to reinforce and perpetuate national origin distinctions. The third policy I want to discuss is citizenship. Until its recent liberalization, German citizenship law was well known for its restrictiveness vis-ä-vis non-German immigrants. What was and remains less well known is that except for political rights, long-settled non-citizen immigrants have possessed rights virtually identical to those of German citizens. Of course, as immigrant populations became more settled, and as a second and an incipient third generation population developed, the lack of political rights became increasingly anomalous. What was distinctive about the response to this anomaly - and indicative of deep-rooted German differential ism - was that the solution was long seen on the left not in terms of incorporating immigrants and their descendants as full citizens, but rather in terms of extending even political rights - along with social, civil, and economic rights - to resident foreigners. Until the early 1990s, there was little interest in the anomalous formal citizenship status of immigrants, but there was considerable interest in extending voting rights to foreigners in local elections, and a large literature addressing this possibility. This was seen as the "progressive" solution -one that would extend the substantive rights of citizenship to immigrants without questioning their "differentness", their foreignness, their otherness.8 Policies in these three domains - schools, social services, and citizenship - and the idioms in which they were rationalized and justified were indicative of a kind of benevolent, paternalistic, and egalitarian (or pseudo-egalitarian) apartheid, an institutionalized separateness, suggested in the oxymoronic phrase "unsere ausländischen Mitbürger" - "our foreign fellow citizens" - that has been a leitmotif of well-meaning public discussions of what continues to be called Ausländerpolitik - politics or policies regarding foreigners - in Germany. Left different] alists of course criticized existing policies on various counts; but they too endorsed this separate-but-equal logic. The Return of Assimilation? 47 It is against this background of deep differentialism that signs of a modest "assimilationist turn" can be discerned in the manner in which citizenship has been legally redefined and politically reconceived in recent years (Joppke 1999: 202-208). Naturalization rules were substantially eased in the early 1990s, and naturalization rates of Turks - extraordinarily low until the late 1980s - have soared. In 1999, naturalization rules were further liberalized. More importantly, the rules for the attribution of citizenship at birth were changed as well, supplementing the previously exclusively descent-based law, founded on the principle of jus sanguinis, with the territorial principle of jus soli. Henceforth, citizenship will be attributed at birth to children born in Germany to foreign parents, one of whom has resided legally in Germany at least eight years. This citizenship will, however, be provisional; in most cases, the child will have to choose either the German or the foreign citizenship at maturity, and renounce the other. The legal changes, increasing naturalization rates, and new ways of thinking and talking about citizenship on the part of Germans and foreigners alike are indicative of a limited but significant "assimilationist turn." Not in the sense that full assimilation is required as a prerequisite for citizenship. To the contrary: the liberalization of naturalization law broke expressly with this principle, previously enshrined in the regulations governing naturalization. The new practices, policies, and discourses surrounding citizenship are assimilationist, rather, in the sense of politically recognizing, legally constituting, and symbolically emphasizing commonality rather than difference. Assimilation, it is worth remembering, means becoming similar, or treating as similar, and this new inflection in the policies and practices of citizenship in the 1990s has involved a modest but significant assimilationist turn in both senses. The US: Assimilation without "assimilationism" Having discussed public discourse in France and public policy in Germany, I turn to a third domain in which one can discern a return of assimilation in recent years: scholarly research. Here I will focus on the United States, though note that in France, too, researchers have shown a renewed interest in assimilation (Tribalat 1996; Todd 1994). In Germany, by contrast, most scholarly research on immigrant integration continues scrupulously to avoid at least the term assimilation, even when it addresses questions that could be seen as falling under this rubric (exceptions include Esser 1980 and Nauck etat. 1997). 48 Rogers Brubaker In the United States, research on Immigrant integration was dominated from its beginnings in the 1920s through the mid-1960s by assimilationist perspectives of one kind or another. Then, from about 1965 to 1985, largely under the impact of external events, the historical and sociological literature - at least the more theoretically ambitious strands of that literature - was characterized mainly by pluralist perspectives, emphasizing and documenting ethnic persistence in a variety of ways.9 Since about 1985, however, one can discern a renewed theoretical concern with assimilation in the scholarly literature (see, for example, Gans 1992; Glazer 1993; Portes and Zhou 1993; Morawska 1994; Kazal 1995; Barkan 1995; Alba and Nee 1997; Rumbaut 1997; Alba 1999). The ethnic persistence literature has made and continues to make valuable contributions. But "a way of seeing," as Kenneth Burke observed, "is also a way of not seeing" (Burke 1954: 40). Focusing on ethnic communities, on ethnically marked places or ethnic organizations rather than on persons or wider social processes, this literature has missed those who moved out of such ethnically marked places, who "disappeared," as Ewa Morawska put it (1994: 83). With its "unexamined assumptions that cultural maintenance is always a good thing, that immigrants as a rule tried to preserve as much of their traditional culture as possible, fand] that ethnocentric Anglo-America equally reflexively resisted both cultural transplantations and assimilation," it has tended to take ethnic communities - places - as opposed to individually experienced adaptation - immigrant lifecourses - as its object of inquiry, and... has tended to focus precisely on those kinds of places -areas of concentrated first-generation settlement - where the odds of finding evidence for ethnic maintenance are greatest. It has sought to restore agency to the immigrant actor, but has not always followed that agency into all the varied paths that it could take. In particular... by confining its focus to ethnic maintenance it neglects to extend its concern for the immigrant as historical actor to the assessment of the immigrant's impact upon society as a whole. We have constructed an oppositional history of virtuous, autonomous, ethnic outsiders interacting minimally with others except in the workplace, outsiders who thereby bear, to be sure, little moral responsibility for the sins of the broader nation, but also, by implication, little significance in its broader history (Conzen 1996: 21). Inwardly focused, the ethnic persistence literature has neglected wider social and cultural processes such as the formation of transethnic (but The Return of Assimilation? 49 often racially closed) working class communities in the early part of the century (Kazal 1995); the spatial dispersion that has accompanied post-World War II suburbanization, in which even recent immigrants have been participating (Alba and Nee 1997: 836-37, 857-62); increasing rates of ethnic intermarriage (Spickard 1989; Alba 1999; Qian 1997); and the dynamic renegotiation of ethnic and racial categories and identifications (Rödiger 1991; Ignatiev 1995; Perlman and Waldinger 1997). All of these processes have led to the blurring or shifting of some ethnic boundaries (Zolberg and Long 1999) in ways that undermine stable ethnic enclosures (Hollinger 1999). The new theorists of assimilation do not simply replicate the old, pre-1965 approaches. The older work - even work as sophisticated as Gordon's - was analytically and normatively Anglo-conformist. It posited, endorsed, and expected assimilation towards an unproblematically conceived white Protestant "core culture." Recent work on assimilation, by contrast, is agnostic about its directions, degrees, and modalities, and ambivalent about its desirability. There is nothing today comparable to the complacent empirical and normative expectancies of mid-century. Of course, this is partly because the notion of a universally acknowledged "core culture" has lost all its plausibility since the late 1960s. This, in turn, has raised the question of the reference population toward which assimilation is said to occur. Characteristic of the newer literature on assimilation is its willingness to consider multiple reference populations and correspondingly segmented forms of assimilation (Portes and Zhou 1993; Zhou 1997; Waters 1994; Neckerman etal. 1999)™ It is no longer true that assimilation (or integration, a term that often, especially in the European context, refers to much the same thing) is "inevitably" conceptualized as occurring "into one, single, indivisible (national) 'state', and one, simple, unitary (national) 'society'" (Favell 2000). Today, concern with assimilation is not necessarily "assimilationist." It implies no global belief in the inevitability or desirability of assimilation. This does not mean that the newer literature on assimilation has no normative thrust. Normative concerns about civic commonality do underlie and inform much work on assimilation today (Alba 1999). But they do not entail any blanket endorsement of assimilation. Some forms of assimilation are indeed widely thought to be desirable. One aspect of linguistic assimilation, for example - the intergenerational acquisition of English at levels sufficient to permit success in schooling, occupational mobility, and full participation in public life - is clearly desirable. But note that this in no way entails the desirability of what Portes and Rumbaut (1990: 209-21) call "subtractive" linguistic 50 Rogers Brubaker assimilation - the intergenerational loss of competence in the language of origin. Some aspects of socio-economic assimilation are also clearly desirable (Hirschman 1983: 403ff; Alba and Nee 1997). Consider, for example, a population with mean income and education levels well below the respective means for the population at large. Surely, assimilation in these domains - in the sense of a shift in the direction of convergence with the income and educational distributions of the wider society -would be desirable for this population, and it is important to know whether and to what extent it is occurring. But the desirability of assimilation in these respects does not imply its desirability in other respects. It does not imply the desirability of complete acculturation, for example; or of full "identificational assimilation" (the "development of a sense of peoplehood based exclusively on the host society" [Gordon 1964: 71, emphasis added]); or of spatial assimilation through suburbanization and the concomitant decline of ethnic neighborhoods; or of full occupational assimilation and the concomitant decline of ethnic niches, enclaves, and professional specializations; or of the erosion of group boundaries through high rates of intermarriage or what Gordon called structural assimilation (participation in the "social cliques, clubs, and institutions of the core society at the primary group level" [Gordon 1964: 80]). My point is not that assimilation in these respects is necessarily undesirable, though evidence - for example, about better health outcomes of infants born to immigrant than to US-born mothers, even after controlling for ethnicity and a variety of socio-economic factors (Rumbaut 1997) - suggests that certain forms of assimilation may indeed be undesirable. This point is forcefully developed in the segmented assimilation literature, which argues that socio-economic success, for second-generation immigrants in predominantly minority inter-city neighborhoods, may depend on resisting assimilation to the surrounding youth milieu, with its adversarial stance toward mainstream culture (Portes and Zhou 1993; Zhou 1997). The broader point is that one can study assimilation in its various domains and directions without being an "assimilationist"; one may be agnostic about its destinations and ambivalent or even skeptical about its desirability. Assimilation is not a single process of the sort envisioned by "straight-line" accounts. Already by Gordon's time, a picture had emerged of assimilation as a complex and only partially interlocking set of processes (see also Yinger 1981). Some of these (notably structural assimilation on Gordon's account and spatial assimilation on some recent accounts [Massey and Denton 1993: 149ff]) bear significantly on The Return of Assimilation? 51 processes in other domains by shaping opportunity structures and contact probabilities. But other domains are at most loosely coupled with one another. Recent accounts are sensitive to the possibilities of different rhythms and trajectories of assimilation - or dissimilation - in different domains (Banton 1983: 144-46). On current understandings, assimilation is always domain-specific and relative to a particular reference population; and the normative stance one takes toward it will also depend on the particular domain and reference population. Conclusion: A concept transformed In all three countries, what I have called "the return of assimilation" has involved a subtle but significant change in perspective. Analytically, this has involved a shift from an overwhelming focus on persisting difference - and on the mechanisms through which such cultural maintenance occurs - to a broader focus that encompasses emerging commonalities as well. Normatively, it has involved a shift from the automatic valorization of cultural differences to a renewed concern with civic integration. This shift in analytical and normative emphasis does not presage a radical reversal. It does not amount to a return to the bad old days of arrogant assimilationism. For while the term "assimilation" has returned, the concept has been transformed. I sketch in conclusion the main elements of this transformation: 1. A shift from organic understandings of assimilation, focusing on an end state of complete absorption, to abstract understandings of assimilation, focusing on a process of becoming similar (in some respect, to some reference population). 2. A shift from transitive to intransitive understandings of assimilation. The former see populations of immigrant origin as moldable, meltable, objects; the latter see persons comprising such populations as active subjects. As such, to be sure, they are not busy consciously "assimilating." Assimilating can, of course, be a deliberate, self-conscious activity; and the poignant - and sometimes tragic - ambiguities and ambivalences bound up with it have been movingly explored by novelists, memoirists, essayists, historians, and even a few sociologists (Bauman 1988; Laitin 1995). Yet for most historians and social scientists, assimilation is an emergent tendential property of social processes at an aggregate level, rather than something that happens (consciously or unconsciously) at the level of individual persons. 52 Rogers Brubaker As an emergent tendency at the aggregate level, assimilation is largely unintended and often invisible; and when it is made visible, it may be lamented, Yet even when it is lamented, the processual tendency we call "assimilation" is not something done to persons, but rather something accomplished by them, not intentionally, but as an unintended consequence of myriad individual actions and choices in particular social, cultural, economic, and political contexts (cf. Alba 1995: 4). 3. The unit within which change occurs - the unit that undergoes assimilation - is not the person but a multi-generational population. Population-level assimilation can occur without any individual-level assimilation. Linguistic assimilation at the population level, for example, can occur without any adult learning a new language, solely through the acquisition of the language of the reference population by children. Of course this is not what ordinarily happens; we do observe some language shift at the level of individual persons. But key changes (in language and in other domains) occur intergenera-tionally; they occur not within persons but within abstractly constructed multigenerational populations, as mw (genealogical) "members" of the population turn out to be different - dissimilare! -from other, older members of the source population, in ways that make them more similar to members of some reference population. 4. A shift from thinking in terms of homogeneous units to thinking in terms of heterogeneous units. Assimilation does not involve a shift from one homogeneous unit to another. It involves, rather, a shift from one mode of heterogeneity - one distribution of properties - to another mode of heterogeneity, i.e. to a distribution of properties more similar to the distribution prevailing in some reference population. 5. A shift in the focus of normative concern informing research on assimilation from cultural to socioeconomic matters. A general openness to cultural diversity, coupled with confidence among specialists - if not always among the wider public - in the continuing robustness of processes of linguistic acculturation (Portes and Schauffler 1994) has alleviated anxieties about cultural dimensions of assimilation. Yet the bifurcation of recent immigrants into high-skill and low-skill segments - at a moment when macroeconomic changes associated with the "hourglass economy" have decreased the rewards to low-skill, uneducated labor - has generated concerns about long-term structural marginalization (Gans 1992; Portes and Zhou 1993; somewhat more optimistic: Waldinger 1996, Perlman and Waldinger 1997). As a normatively charged concept, assimilation, in this sense, The Return of Assimilation? 53 is opposed not to difference but to segregation, ghettoization, and marginalization. 6. A shift from a holistic approach that conceptualized assimilation towards a taken-for-granted reference population - the "core culture" or "national society" as a whole - to a disaggregated approach that discards the notion of assimilation as a single process, considers multiple reference populations, and envisions distinct processes occurring in different domains. This has entailed a shift from the monodimensional question, "how much assimilation?" to the multidimensional question, "assimilation in what respect, over what period of time, and to what reference population?" U has also entailed a shift from an assimilationist understanding of assimilation - a global empirical expectation and normative endorsement of assimilation - to an agnostic stance, varying by domain and reference population, concerning both the likelihood and the desirability of assimilation. Reformulated in this manner, and divested of its "assimilationist" connotations, the concept of assimilation - if not the term itself - seems not only useful but indispensable. It enables us to ask questions about the domains and degrees of emergent similarities, and persisting differences, between multigenerational populations of immigrant origin and particular reference populations. There are good reasons for us to want to ask such questions, regardless of whether we applaud or lament such emerging similarities. Naturally, to pose such questions is only a beginning. Assimilation is not a theory; it is simply a concept. But it is a concept we can ill do without. Acknowledgments This chapter first appeared in Ethnic and Racial Studies 24[4](July 2001): 531-48, © 2001 Taylor & Francis Ltd. Thanks to Roger Waldinger for his detailed comments and criticisms on an earlier draft, too many of which remain unaddressed. Thanks also to Andreas Wimmer, Jennifer Lee, Daniel Wölk, and members of my nationalism workshop for helpful comments, and to Christian joppke, who organized the conference on "Integrating Immigrants in Liberal States" European University Institute, Florence, May 8-9, 1998, for which an initial version of the paper was prepared. Research support from the Comparative Immigration and Integration Program of the Center for German and European Studies at the University of California, Berkeley is gratefully acknowledged. 54 Rogers Brubaker Notes 1 Glazer's title, to be sure, was wry, not celebratory; it was intended to acknowledge, not to endorse, the current ascendancy of multiculturalism. 2 I refer to Imperial Germany rather than Nazi Germany because Nazi policies were, of course, murderously dissimilationist rather than assimilationist. 3 There is another transitive use of "assimilate" that is less problematic, nor-matively and analytically. This is the use of "assimilate" to mean treat similarly rather than make similar. To assimilate X's to Y's in one's dealings with them is to treat them similarly rather than differently. From a differentialist normative perspective, to be sure, such similarity of treatment can be problematic. But in general "treating similarly" is a transitive meaning of "assimilate" quite distinct from, and normatively and analytically less suspect than, "making similar." 4 For sophisticated discussions of the idea of integration, see Favell (2000) and Bauböck (2001). 5 Although this program, committed to cultural maintenance in the interest of keeping the option of "return" open to immigrants, is strongly differential ist in orientation, it has not been very popular. Even at the peak differentialist moment, in the early 1980s, only about 20 percent of eligible students participated (Boyzon-Fradet 1992: 158); by 1992-93, only 12 percent of Algerian citizens enrolled in French primary schools - and a considerably smaller proportion of students of Algerian origin - participated (Vermes 1997). 6 Differentialist discourse concerned not only populations of immigrant origin but also regional minority cultures; on the latter see Giordan (1982). 7 German discourse on immigration and its sequels, too, has been strongly differentialist. On the historical roots of this differentialist discursive tradition, see Brubaker (1992: 3-17); for contemporary manifestations, see Joppke (1999: 188-89). 8 On the still more "progressive" differentialist solution - the proposed Niederlassungsgesetz or settlement law that would grant all citizenship rights, including the right to vote in national elections, on the basis of residence rather than formal citizenship - see Joppke (1999: 192-93). 9 A considerable amount of mainstream sociological research, to be sure, continued throughout this period to study processes of assimilation; for reviews see Price (1969), Hirschman (1983). 10 Some earlier literature, while positing acculturation to a single core culture, can be said to have anticipated the notion of segmented assimilation by conceptualizing structural assimilation and intermarriage among European immigrants as occurring within confessional boundaries (Kennedy 1944 [but see also the critique of Peach 1980]; Gordon 1964). References Alba, Richard D. (3 995). "Assimilation's Quiet Tide." Public Interest, 119: 3-18. --------- (1999). "Immigration and the American Realities of Assimilation and Multiculturalism." Sociological Forum 14(1): 3-25. Alba, Richard D. and Victor Nee (1997). "Rethinking Assimilation Theory for a New Era of Immigration," International Migration Review 31(4): 826-74. The Return of Assimilation? 55 Älund, Aleksandra and Carl-Ulrik Schierup (1991). Paradoxes of Multiculturalism: Essays on Swedish Society. Aldershot, UK: Avebury. Banton, Michael (1983). Racial and Ethnic Competition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Barkan, Elliott R. (1995). "Race, Religion, and Nationality in American Society: A Model of Ethnicity - From Contact to Assimilation." Journal of American Ethnic History 14(2): 38-101. Bauböck, Rainer (2001). "Integration von Einwanderern - Reflexionen zum Begriff und seine Anwendungsmöglichkeiten." Die Integration von Einwanderern, vol. 2: Ein Index rechtlicher Diskriminierung, ed. Harald Waldrauch. Frankfurt: Campus Verlag. Bauman, Zygmunt (1988). "Exit Visas and Entry Tickets: Paradoxes of Jewish Assimilation." Telos, 77: 45-77. Boyzon-Fradet, Danielle (1992). "The French Education System: Springboard or Obstacle to Integration?", pp. 148-66 in Immigrants in Two Democracies: The French and American Experience, eds. Donald L. Horowitz and Gerard Noiriel. New York: New York University Press. Brosted, Jens etal. (1985). Native Power: The Quest for Autonomy and Nationhood of Indigenous Peoples. Bergen: Univers itetsforlaget. Broszat, Martin (1972). Zweihundert fahre deutsche Polenpolitik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Brubaker, Rogers (1992). Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Brubaker, Rogers and Frederick Cooper (2000). "Beyond 'Identity'." Theory and Society, 29(1): 1-47. Burke, Kenneth (1954). Permanence and Change: An Anatomy of Purpose. Los Altos, CA: Hermes Publications. Castles, Steven, Heather Booth, and Tina Wallace (1984). Here for Good: Western Europe's New Ethnic Minorities. London: Pluto Press. Conzen, Kathleen N. (1996). "Thomas and Znaniecki and the Historiography of American Immigration." Journal of American Ethnic History, 16(1): 16-26. D'Souza, Dinesh (1991). Illiberal Education: The Politics of Race anil Sex on Campus. New York: Free Press. Esser, Hartmut (1980). Aspekte der Wanderungssoziologie: Assimilation und Integration von Wanderern, ethnischen Gruppen und Minderheiten: eine handlungstheoretische Analyse. Darmstadt, Neuwied: Luchterhand. Favell, Adrian (2000). "Integration Policy and Integration Research in Europe: A Review and Critique." Citizenship: Comparisons and Perspectives, eds. Alex Aleinikoff and Doug Klusmeyer. Washington DC; Brookings Institute. Finkielkraut, Alain (1987). La défaite de la pensée. Paris: Gallimard. Gans, Herbert (1992). "Second-Generation Decline: Scenarios for the Economic and Ethnic Features of the Post-1965 American Immigrants." Ethnic and Racial Studies 15(2): 173-92. Giordan, Henri (1982). Démocratie culturelle et droit ä la difference. Paris: La Documentation francaise. Gitlin, Todd (1995). The Twilight of Common Dreams: Why America Is Wracked by Culture Wars. New York: Henry Holt. Glazer, Nathan (1978). Affirmative Discrimination: Ethnic Inequality and Public Policy. New York: Basic Books. 56 Rogers Brubaker ---------(1993). "Is Assimilation Dead?" Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 530: 122-36. --------- (1997). We Are All Multiculturalists Now, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Glazer, Nathan and Daniel P. Moynihan (1963). Beyond the Melting Pot: The Negroes, Puerto Ricans, Jews, Italians, and Irish of New York City. Cambridge: MIT Press. Gleason, Philip (1980). "American Identity and Americanization." pp, 31-58 in Harvard Encyclopedia of American Ethnic Groups, ed. Stephan Thernstrom. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University. Gordon, Milton M. (1964). Assimilation in American Life: The Role of Race, Religion, and National Origins. New York: Oxford University Press. Hirschman, Charles (1983). "America's Melting Pot Reconsidered." Annual Review of Sociology 9: 397-423. Hollinger, David A. (1995). Postethnic America: Beyond Multiatlturalism. New York: Basic Books. ---------(1997). "The Disciplines and the Identity Debates, 1970-1995." Daedalus 126(1): 333-51. ---------(1999). "Authority, Solidarity, and the Political Economy of Identity: The Case of the United States." Diacritics 29(4): 116-27. Howe, Stephen (1998). Afŕocentrism: Mythical Pasts and Imagined Homes. New York: Verso. Ignatiev, Noel (1995). How the Irish Became White, New York: Routledge. Irigaray, Luce (1993). Je, tu, nous: Toward a Culture of 'Difference. New York: Routledge. Johnston, Jill (1973). Lesbian Nation. New York: Harper Row. Joppke, Christian (1999). Immigration and the Nation-State: The United States, Germany, and Great Britain. New York: Oxford University Press. Kazal, Russell A. (1995). "Revisiting Assimilation: The Rise, Fall, and Reappraisal of a Concept in American Ethnic History." The American Historical Review 100(2): 437. Keating, Michael (1996). Nations Against the State: The New Politics of Nationalism in Quebec, Catalonia and Scotland. New York: St Martin's Press - now Palgrave Macmillan. Kennedy, Ruby J.R. (1944). "Single or Triple Melting Pot? Intermarriage Trends in New Haven, 1870-1940." American Journal of Sociology 49(4): 331-39. Koopmans, Ruud and Paul Statham (2000). "Migration and Ethnic Relations as a Field of Political Contention: An Opportunity Structure Approach." Challenging Immigration and Ethnic Relations Politics: Comparative European Perspectives, eds. Ruud Koopmans and Paul Statham. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kymlicka, Will (1995). Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Laitin, David D. (1995). "Marginality: A Microperspective." Rationality and Society 7(1): 31-57. Lane, Harlan (1992). The Mask of Benevolence: Disabling the Deaf Community. New York: A.A. Knopf. Massey, Douglas S. and Nancy A. Denton (1993). American Apartheid: Segregation and the Making of the Underclass. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Morawska, Ewa (1994). "In Defense of the Assimilation Model." Journal of American Ethnic History 13(2): 76-87. Nash, Gary B., Charlotte Crabtree, and Ross E. Dunn (1997). History on Trial: Culture Wars and the Teaching of the Past. New York: A.A. Knopf. The Return of Assimilation? 57 Nauck, Bernhard etat. (1997). "Familiäre Netzwerke, intergenerative Transmission und Assimilationsprozesse bei türkischen Migrantenfamilien." Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie 49(3): 477-99. Neckerman, Kathryn M., Prudence Carter, and Jennifer Lee (1999). "Segmented Assimilation and Minority Cultures of Mobility." Ethnic and Racial Studies 22(6): 945-65. Noiriel, Gerard (1988). Le creuset francais: Histoire de ľimmigration XIXe-XXe siecles. Paris: Seuil. Peach, Ceri (1980). "Which Triple Melting Pot? A Re-Examination of Ethnic Intermarriage in New Haven." Ethnic and Racial Studies 3(1): 1-1.6. Perlmann, Joel and Roger Waldinger (1997). "Second Generation Decline? Children of Immigrants, Past and Present-A Reconsideration." International Migration Review 31(4): 893-922. Portes, Alejandro and Ruben G. Rumbaut (1990). Immigrant America: A Portrait Berkeley: University of California Press. Portes, Alejandro and Richard Schauffler (1994). "Language and the Second Generation: Bilingualism Yesterday and Today." International Migration Review 28(4): 640-61. Portes, Alejandro and Min Zhou (1993). "The New Second Generation: Segmented Assimilation and Its Variants." Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 530: 74-96. Price, Charles (1969). "The Study of Assimilation." pp. 181-237 in Migration, ed. J.A.Jackson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Puskeppeleit, Jürgen and Dietrich Thränhardt (1990). Vom betreuten Ausländer zum gleichberechtigten Büger. Freiburg: Lambertus. Cyan, Zhenchao (1997). "Breaking the Racial Barriers: Variations in Interracial Marriage Between 1980 and 1990." Demography 42(2): 263-76. Rödiger, David R. (1991). The Wages of Whiteness. London: Verso. Rumbaut, Rubén G. (1997). "Assimilation and Its Discontents: Between Rhetoric and Reality." International Migration Review 31(4): 923-60. Schnapper, Dominique (1992). ĽEurope des immigrés. Paris: Francois Bourin. Soininen, Maritta (1999). "The 'Swedish Model' as an Institutional Framework for Immigrant Membership Rights." Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 25(4): 685-702. Spickard, Paul R. (1989). Mixed Blood. Madison, Wl: University of Wisconsin Press. Taguieff, Pierre-André (1994). Sur la nouvelle droite: jalons d'une analyse critique. Paris: Descartes & Cie. ---------(1996). La République menacée. Paris: Textuel. Thränhardt, Dietrich (2000). "Conflict, Consensus, and Policy Outcomes: Immigration and Integration in Germany and the Netherlands." Challenging Immigration and Ethnic Relations Politics: Comparative European Perspectives, eds. Ruud Koopmans and Paul Statham. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Todd, Emmanuel (1994). Le destin des immigrés: assimilation et segregation dans les démocraties occidentales. Jacob, Paris: Seuil. Tribalat, Michěle (1996). De ľimmigration ä ľassimilation: enqu&te sur les populations ďorigine étrangäre en France. Paris: La Découverte. Vermes, Genevieve (1997). "La dynamique interculturelle dans ľéducation en France." DiversCitéĹangues II 58 Rogers Brubaker Waldinger, Roger (1996). "Ethnicity and Opportunity in the Plural City." pp. 445-70 in Ethnic Los Angeles, eds. Roger Waldinger and Mehdi Bozorgmehr. New York: Rüssel Sage Foundation. Waters, Mary (1994). "Ethnic and Racial Identities of Second-Generation Black Immigrants in New York City." International Migration Review 28(4): 795-820. Weber, Eugen (1976). Peasants into Frenchmen: The Modernization of Rural France, 1870-1914. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Wieviorka, Michel (1996). "Culture, societě et democratic" pp. 11-60 in Une société fragmentée?: le multiculturalisme en debat, ed. Michel Wieviorka. Paris: Editions La Découverte, Yinger, J.M. (1981). "Toward a Theory of Assimilation and Dissimilation." Ethnic and Racial Studies 4(3): 249-64. Young, Iris M. (1990). Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Zhou, Min (1997). "Segmented Assimilation: Issues, Controversies, and Recent Research on the New Second Generation." International Migration Review 31(4): 975-1008. Zolberg, Aristide R. and Long L. Woon (1999). "Why Islam Is Like Spanish: Cultural Incorporation in Europe and the United States." Politics and Society 27(1): 5-38. 3 The Rise and Fall of Multiculturalism: The Case of the Netherlands Han Entzinger Wake up any expert on immigrant integration in the middle of the night and ask that person to name a country known for its multiculturalism. Ten to one that the answer will be Canada, Australia or the Netherlands. In recent years, however, multiculturalism has come increasingly under fire in all three, but probably most of all in the Netherlands. In this chapter 1 will first analyze the rise and fall of Dutch multiculturalist policies for immigrants. I will then place the recent turnaround in the perspective of the current debate on citizenship and multiculturalism, the general theme of this book. Can public policy in the Netherlands indeed be seen as an example of a renewed emphasis on citizenship and shared values in response to earlier tendencies towards pôstnationalism and multiculturalism? If so, what are the reasons for this change, what arguments have been put forward by different sides, and how are current trends likely to evolve further? Migrants in the Netherlands For all but one of the past 40 years the number of people settling in the Netherlands has been higher than the number of.those departingjAs a consequence, 1.4 million residents - almost 9 percent of the population -now are foreign born (from parents who themselves are also foreign born). If we include persons born in the Netherlands with one or two foreign-born parents the percentage goes up from 9 to 17. This means that just over one in every six persons living in the country has an immigrant background or a parent to whom this applies. This is not unusual by current West European standards, but not everyone realizes that the level in the United States is roughly the same. The number of foreign passport holders in the Netherlands is considerably lower than the number of 59