1 The Concept(s) of Culture WILLIAM H. SEWELL, JR. The aim of this chapter is to reflect upon the concept-or more properly the concepts-of culture in contemporary academic discourse. Trying to clarify what we mean by culture seems both imperative and impossible at a moment like the present, when the study of culture is burgeoning in virtually all fields of the human sciences. Although I glance at the varying uses of "culture" in a number of disciplines, my reflection is based above all on the extensive debates that have occurred in anthropology over the past two decades-debates'., in which some have questioned the very utility of the concept.' I feel strongly that it remains as useful, indeed essential, as ever. But given the cacophony of contemporary discourse about culture, I also believe that the concept needs some reworking and clarification.s, The current volatility of the concept of culture sharply contrasts with the situation in the early 1970s, when I first got interested in a cultural approach to social history. At that time it was clear that if you wanted to learn about culture, you turned to the anthropologists. And while they by no means spoke in a single voice, they shared a Widespread consensus both about the meaning of culture and about its centrality to the anthropological enterprise. I began borrowing the methods and insights of cultural anthropology as a means of learning more about nineteenth-century French workers.Ji Cultural analysis, I hoped, would enable me to understand the If 'I' meaning of workers' practices that I had been unable toget at by using quantitative and positivist methods-my standard tool kit as a practitioner of what was then called "the new social history." 2 I ex­ '~i perienced the encounter with cultural anthropology as a tum from a hardheaded, utilitarian, and empiricist materialism-which had both liberal and marxisant faces-to a wider appreciation of the 35 37]6 Willialll H 5cl/'('II, [r. range of human possibilities, both in the past and in the present. Convinced that there was more to life than the relentless pursuit of wealth, status, and power, I felt that cultural anthropology could show us how to get ill that "more."} Anthropology at the time had a virtual monopoly on the concept of culture. In political science and sociology, culture was associated with the by then utterly sclerotic Parsonian theoretical synthesis. The embryonic "cultural studies" movement was still confined to a single research center in Birmingham. And literary studies were still fixated on canonical literary texts-s-nlthough the methods of studying them were being revolutionized by the importation of "french" structurnlist and poststructuralist theory. Moreover, the mid-rooos to the mid-1970S marked the glory years uf American cultural anthropology, which may be said to have reached its apotheosis with the publication of Clifford Ceertzs phenomenally influentialllltcrp,·etl7tiOlI of Cult urcs in 197J. 1 Not only did anthropology have no serious rivals in the study of culture, but the creativity and prestige of cultural anthropology were at a very high point. During the 1980s and 1990s, the intellectual ecology of the study of culture has been transformed by a vast expansion of work on culture-indeed, a kind of academic culture mania has set in. The new interest in culture has swept over a wide range of academic disciplines and specialties. The history of this advance differs in timing and con tent in each field, but the cumulative effects are undeniable. In literary studies, which were already being transformed by French theory in the 1970s, the 1980s marked a turn to a vastly wider range of texts, quasi-texts, paratexts, and text analogs. If, as Derrida declared, nothing is extratextual ("il n'y a pas de hors-texte"), literary critics could direct their theory-driven gaze upon semiotic products of all kinds-legal documents, political tracts, soap operas, histories, talk shows, popular romances-and seek out their intertextualities." Consequently, as such "new historicist" critics as Stephen Greenblatt and Louis Montrose recognize, literary study is increasinglv becoming the study of cultures." In history the ea rly and rather self-conscious bt)!T\1\ving from anthropology has been followed by a theoretically heterogeneous rush to the study of culture, one madded as much on literary studies or the work of Michel Foucault ClSon anthropology. As a consequence, the self-confident "new social hisTile Conceptts) «[Culmre tory" of the 1960s and 1970S was succeeded by an equally selfconfident "new cultural history" in the 1980s/ In the late 19708, an emerging "sociology of culture" began by applying standard sociological methods to studies of the production and marketing of cultural artifacts-music, art, drama, and literature. By the late 1980s, the work of cultural sociologists had broken out of the study of culture-producing institutions and moved toward studying the place of meaning in social life more generally, Feminism, which in the 1970S was concerned above all to document women's experiences, has increasingly turned to analyzing the discursive production of gender difference. Since the mid-rosos the new quasi-discipline of cultural studies has grown explosively in a variety of different academic niches-for example, in programs or departments of film studies, literature, performance studies, or communications. In political science, which is well known for its propensity to chase headlines, interest in cultural questions has been revived by the recent prominence of religious fundamentalism, nationalism, and ethnicity, which look like the most potent sources of political conflict in the contemporary world. This frenetic rush to the study of culture has everywhere been bathed, to a greater or lesser extent, in the pervasive transdisciplinary influence of the French poststructuralist trinity of Lacan. Derrida, and Foucault. It is paradoxical that as discourse about culture becomes ever ~ more pervasive and multifarious, anthropology, the discipline that invented the concept-or at least shaped it into something like its present form-is somewhat ambivalently backing away from its long-standing identification with culture as its keyword and central symbol. For the past decade and a half, anthropology has been rent by a particularly severe identity crisis, which has been manifested in anxiety about the discipline's epistemology, rhetoric, methodological procedures, and political implications," The reasons for the crisis are many-liberal and radical guilt about anthropology's association with Euro-American colonialism, the disappearance of the supposedly "untouched" or "primitive" peoples who were the favored subjects for classic ethnographies, the rise of "native" ethnographers who contest the right of European and American scholars to tell the "truth" about their people, and the general loss of confidence in the possibility of objectivity that has attended poststructuralism and 39}8 Willinll1 H Sewell,Jr. postmodernism. As anthropology's most central and distinctive concept, "culture" has become a suspect term among critical anthropologists-who cla im that both in academia and in public discourse, talk about culture tends to essentialize, exoticize, and stereotype those whose ways of life are being described and to naturalize their differences from white middle-class Euro-Americans. If Geertz's phrase "The Interpretation of Cultures" was the watchword of anthropology in the 1970s, Lila Abu-Lughods "Writing against Culture" more nearly sums up the mood of the late 1980s and the 1990S.9 As [ohn Brightman points out in his superb commentary on the recent disputes about culture in anthropology, the anthropological critics of the 1980s and 1990S have exhibited Widespread "lexical avoidance behavior," either placing the term "culture" in quotation marks when it is used, refusing to use "culture" as a noun while continuing to use it as an adjective (as in "cultural anthropology"), or replacing it with alternative lexerues such as "habitus," "hegemony," or "discourse." HI This emerging anthropological tabu seems to me mistaken on two counts. First, it is based on the implicit assumption that anthropology "owns" the lexeme and that it is therefore responsible for any abuses that might be pcrpet ratcd by others employing the term. Second, it assumes that anthropological abstention from the use of the lexerne will magically abolish such abuses. The truth is that the term has escaped all possibility of control by anthropologists: whatever lexical practices the anthropologists may adopt, talk about culture will continue to thrive-in both abusive and acceptable ways-in a wide range of other academic disciplines and in ordinary language as well. Moreover, as Brightman again points out, even the critical anthropologists find it impossible to give up the COIIceptof culture, as opposed to the lexeme. James Clifford's lament that ~; , "culture is a deeply compromised concept that I cannot yet do without" seems emblematic of the unresolved ambivalence: the concept is compromised and he hopes in the future to do without it, but because it continues to perform valuable intellectual work the fateful act of renunciation is indefinitely deferred."! If, as I believe, Clifford is right that we G\t1IHlt do without a concept of culture, I think we should try to shape it into one we can work with. We need to modify, rearticulato, and revivify the concept, retaining and reshaping what is useful and discarding what is not. Tile Concepits) of Culture WHAT DO WE MEAN BY CULTURE? Writing in 198], Raymond Williams declared that "culture is one of the two or three most complicated words in the English language."12 Its complexity has surely not decreased since then. I have neither the competence nor the inclination to trace out the full range of meanings of "culture" in contemporary academic discourse. But some attempt to sort out the different usages of the word seems essential, and it must begin by distinguishing two fundamentally different meanings of the term. In one meaning, culture is a theoretically defined category or as­ pect of social life that must be abstracted out from the complex real­ ity of human existence. Culture in this sense is always contrasted to some other equally abstract aspect or category of social life that is not culture, such as economy, politics, or biology. To designate some­ thing as culture or as cultural is to claim it for a particular academic discipline or subdiScipline-for example, anthropology..or cultural sociology-or for a particular style or styles of analysis-for ex­ ample, structuralism, ethno-science, componential analysis, decon­ struction, or hermeneutics. Culture in this sense-as an abstract ana­ lytical category-only takes the singular. Whenever we speak of "cultures," we have moved to the second fundamental meaning. In that second meaning, culture stands for a concrete and bounded world of beliefs and practices. Culture in this sense is com­ monly assumed to belong to or to be isomorphic with a "society" or with some dearly identifiable subsocietal group. We may speak of "American culture" or "Samoan culture," or of "middle-class cul­ ture" or "ghetto culture."13 The contrast in this usage is not between .' culture and not-culture but between one culture and another-between American, Samoan, French, and Bororo cultures, or between middle-class and upper-class cultures, or between ghetto and mainstream cultures. This distinction between culture as theoretical category and culture as concrete and bounded body of beliefs and practices is, as far as I can discern, seldom made. Yet it seems to me crucia I for thinking clearly about cultural theory. It should be clear, for example, that Ruth Benedict's concept of cultures as sharply distinct and highly integrated refers to culture in the second sense, while Claude Levi­ 41WiJlirJ11l H SCil'df, Jr.4° Strauss's notion that cultural meaning is structured by systems of oppositions is a claim about culture in the first sense, Hence their theories of "culture" arc, strictly speaking, incommensurate: they refer to different conceptual universes. Failure to recognize this distinction between two fundamentally different meanings of the term has real consequences for contemporary cultural theory; some of the impasses of theoretical discourse in contemporary anthropology are attributable precisely to an unrecognized elision of the two, TIlUS, a dissatisfaction with "Benedictine" etlmographies that present cultures as uniformly well-bounded and coherent has led to what seem to me rather confused attacks on "the culture concept" in generalatl,lcks that [ail to distinguish Benedictine claims about the tight integrillion of cultures from Levi-Straussian claims about the semiotic coherence of culture as a system of meaningsJ ' Conversely, anthropologists who defend the culture concept also tend to conflate the two meanings, regarding claims that cultures are rent with fissures or that their boundaries are porous as implying an abandonment of the concept of culture altogether. Here, 1 will be concerned primarily with culture in the first sense-culture as a category of social life. One must have a clear conception of culture at this abstract level in order to deal with the more concrete theoretical question of how cultural differences are patterned and bounded in space and time. Once 1have sketched out my own ideas about what an adequate abstract theory of culture might look like, I will return to the question of culture as a bounded universe of beliefs and practices-to the question of cultures in the Benedictine sense. CULTURE AS A CATEGORY OF SOCIAL LIFE Cultu re as a category of social life has itself been conceptualized in a number of different ways. Let me begin by specifying some of these different conceptualizations, moving from those I do not find especially useful to those 1 find more adequate. Cultnre t1~ learned bclnnnor. Culture in this sense is the whole body of f'ri1ctice~, beliefs, inst itut ions, customs, habits, myths, and so on built up by humans and passed on from gcneration to genemtion.ln this usage, culture is contrasted to nature: its possession is what distinguishes LIS from other animals. When anthropologists were strugrile Conceptis) a/Culture gling to establish that differences between societies were not based on biological differences between their populations-that is, on race-a definition of culture as learned behavior made sense. But now that racial arguments have virtually disappeared from anthropological discourse, a concept of culture so broad as this seems impossibly vague; it provides no particular angle or analytical purchase on the study of social life. A narrower and consequently more useful conceptualization of culture emerged in anthropology during the second quarter of the twentieth century and has been dominant in the social sciences generally since World War II. It defines culture not as all learned behavior but as that category or aspect of learned behavior that is concerned with meaning. But the concept of culture-as-meaning is in fact a family of related concepts; meaning may be used to specify a cul'. tural realm or sphere in at least four distinct ways, each of which is defined in contrast to somewhat differently conceptualized noncultural realms or spheres. Culture as all institutional sphere devoted to the making of meaning. This conception of culture is based on the assumption that social formations are composed of clusters of institutions devoted to specialized activities. These clusters can be assigned to variously defined institutional spheres-most conventionally, spheres of politics, economy, society, and culture. Culture is the sphere devoted specifically to the production, circulation, and use of meanings. The cultural sphere may in turn be broken down into the subspheres of which it is composed: say, of art, music, theater, fashion, literature, religion, media, and education. The study of culture, if culture is defined in this way, is the study of the activities that take placewithin these institutionally defined spheres and of the meanings produced in them. This conception of culture is particularly prominent in the discourses of sociology and cultural studies, but it is rarely used in anthropology. Its roots probably reach back to the strongly evaluative conception of culture as a sphere of "high" or "uplifting" artistic and intellectual activity, a meaning that Raymond Wi! Iiams tells us came into prominence in the nineteenth century.IS Bu t in contemporary academic discourse, this usage normally lacks such evaluative and hierarchizing implications. The dominant style of work in American sociology of culture has been demystifying: its typical approach has 42 43Williall1 H. Setccll, Jr. been 10 uncover the largely self-aggrandizing, class-interested, rnanipulntive, or professionalizing institutional dynamics that undergird prestigious museums, artistic styles, symphony orchestras, or philosophical schools. And cultural studies, which has taken as its particular mission the appreciation of cultural forms disdained by the spokesmen of high culture-rock music, street fashion, crossdressing, shopping malls, Disneyland, soap operas-employs this same basic definition of culture. It merely trains its analytical attenlion on spheres of meaning production ignored by previous analysts and regarded as debased by elite tastemakers. TIle problem with such a concept of culture is that it focuses only on a ceriain range of meanings, produced in a certain range of institutional locations-c-on self-consciously "cultural" institutions and on expressive, artistic, and literary systems of meanings. This use of the concept is to some extent complicit with the Widespread notion that meanings arc of minimal importance in the other "noncultural" institutional spheres: that in political or economic spheres, meanings are merely superstructural excrescences. And since institutions in political and economic spheres control the great bulk of society's resources, viewing culture as a distinct sphere of activity milY in the end simply confirm the Widespread presupposition in the "harder" social sciences that culture is merely froth on the tides of society. 111e rise of a cultural sociology that limited itself to studying "cultural" institutions effected a partition of subject matter that was very unfavornble to the cultural sociologists. Indeed, only the supercession of this restrictive concept of culture has made possible the explosive growth of the subfield of cultural sociology in the past decade. Culture as creativity 01' ascllcy. This usage of culture has grown up particularly in traditions that posit a powerful "material" determinism-most notably Marxism and American sociology. Over the past three decades or so, scholars working within these traditions have carved out a conception of culture as a realm of creativity that escRpes from the otherwise pervasive determination of social action by economic or social structures. In the Marxist tradition, it was probably E. r.Thompson's !v1I1ki"S (:fHit'Ellglislr Workillg Class that first conceptualized culture as a realm of agency, and it is particularly English Marxists-v-for example, Paul Willis in Learning to Labor-who hilH' elaborated this conccption.!" But the defining opposition on which this concept of culture rests- culture versus structure-has The Conceptts) o/Culture also become pervasive in the vernacular of American sociology. One clear sign that American anthropologists and sociologists have different conceptions of culture is that the opposition between culture and structure-an unquestioned commonplace in contemporary sociological discourse-is nonsensical in anthropology. In my opinion, identifying culture with agency and contrasting it with structure merely perpetuates the same determinist materialism that "culturalist" Marxists were reacting against in the first place. It exaggerates both the implacability of socioeconomic determinations and the free play of symbolic action. Both socioeconomic and cultural processes are blends of structure and agency. Cultural actionsay, performing practical jokes or writing poems-is necessarily constrained by cultural structures, such as existing linguistic, visual, or ludic conventions. And economic action-such as the manufacture or repair of automobiles-is impossible without the exercise of creativity and agency. The particulars of the relationship between structure and agency may differ in cultural and economic processes, but assigning either the economic or the cultural exclusively to structure or to agency is a serious category error. This brings us to the two concepts of culture that I regard as most fruitful and that I see as currently struggling for dominance: the concept of culture as a system of symbols and meanings, which was hegemonic in the 1960s and 1970S'and the concept of culture as practice, which has become increasingly prominent in the 1980s and 1990s. Cultureasasystem ofsymbolsand meanings. This has been the dominant concept of culture in American anthropology since the 1960s. It was made famous above all by Clifford Geertz, who used the term "cultural system" in the titles of some of his most notable essays.!" The notion was also elaborated by David Schneider, whose writings had a considerable influence within anthropology but lacked Geertz's interdisciplinary appeal." Geertz and Schneider derived the term from Talcott Parsons's usage, according to which the cultural system, a system of symbols and meanings, was a particular "level of abstraction" of social relations. It was contrasted to the "social system," which was a system of norms and institutions, and to the "personality system," which was a system of rnotivations.!? Geertz and Schneider especially wished to distinguish the cultural system from the social system. To engage in cultural analysis, for them, was to 44 45IVi/Halll H. Sf1l'cll, Jr. abstract the meaningful aspect of human action out from the flow of concrete interactions. The point of conceptualizing culture as a system of symbols and meanings is to disentangle, for the purpose of analysis, the semiotic influences on action from the other sorts of influences-demographic, geographical, biological, technological, economic, and so on-that they are necessarily mixed with in any concrete sequence of behavior. Ceertzs and Schneider's post-Parsonian theorizations of cultural systems were by no means the only available models for symbolic anthropology in the 1960s and 1970s. The works of Victor Turner, whose theoretical origins were in the largely Durkheirnian British school of social anthropology, were also immensely influential." Claude Levi-Strauss and his many followers provided an entire alternative model of culture as a system of symbols and meaningsconceptualized, following Saussure, as signifiers and signifieds. Moreover, all these anthropological schools were in a sense manifes, tations of a much broader "linguistic turn" in the human sciencesa diverse but sweeping attempt to specify the structures of human symbol systems and to indicate their profound influence on human behavior. One thinks above all of such French "structuralist" thinkers as Roland Barthes, Jacques Lacan, or the early Michel Foucault. What all of these approaches had in common was an insistence on the systematic nature of cultural meaning and the autonomy of symbol systems-their distinctness from and irreducibility to other fealures of social life. They all abstracted a realm of pure signification out from the complex messiness of social life and specified its internal coherence and deep logic. Their practice of cultural analysis consequently tended to be more or less synchronic and formalist. Culture nspractice. The past decade and a half has witnessed a pervasive reaction against the concept of culture as a system of symbols and meanings, which has taken place in various disciplinary 10cations and intellectual traditions and under many different slogans-for example, "practice," "resistance," "history," "politics," or "culture as tool ki L" Analysts working under all these banners object 10 a portrayal of culture as logical, coherent, shared, uniform, and static. Instead lhey insist that culture is a sphere of practical activity c;hot through by willful action, power relations, struggle, contradiclion, and change, Tile COllcepf(s) of Culture In anthropology, Sherry Ortner in 1984 remarked on the turn to politics, history, and agency, suggesting Pierre Bourdieu's key term "practice" as an appropriate label for this emerging sensibility. Two years later the publication of James Clifford and George Marcus's collection Writing Cultureannounced to the public the crisis of anthropology's culture concept." Since then, criticisms of the concept of culture as a system of symbols and meanings have flowed .thick and fast. The most notable work in anthropology has argued for the contradictory, politically charged, changeable, and fragmented character of meanings-both meanings produced in the societies being studied and meanings rendered in anthropological texts. Recent work in anthropology has in effect recast culture as aperformstive term. . Not surprisingly, this emphasis on the performative aspect of culture is compatible with the work of most cultural historians. Historians are generally uncomfortable with synchronic concepts. As they took up the study of culture, they subtly-but usually without comment-altered the concept by stressing the contradictoriness and malleability of cultural meanings and by seeking out the mechanisms by which meanings were transformed. The battles in history have been over a different issue, pitting those who claim that historical change should be understood as a purely cultural or discursive process against those who argue for the significance of economic and social determinations or for the centrality of concrete "experience" in understanding it.22 Sociologists, for rather different reasons, have also favored a more performative conception of culture. Given the hegemony of a strongly causalist methodology and philosophy of science in contemporary sociology, cultural sociologists have felt a need to demonstrate that culture has causal efficacy in order to gain recognition for ,~, their fledgling subfield. This has led many of them to construct cul­ ture as a collection of variables whose influence on behavior can be rigorously compared to that of such standard sociological variables as class, etlmicity, gender, level of education, economic interest, and the like. As a result, they have moved away from earlier Weberian, Durkheimian, or Parsonian conceptions of culture as rather vague and global value orientations to what Ann Swidler has termed a "tool kit" composed of a "repertoire" of "strategies of action." 21 For 4746 William H. Setrcll, Jr. many cultural sociologists, then, culture is not a coherent system of symbols and meanings but a diverse collection of "tools" that, as the metaphor indicates, are to be understood as means for the performance of action. Because these tools are discrete, local, and intended for specific purposes, they can be deployed as explanatory variables in a way that culture conceived as a translocal, generalized system of meanings C<11Ul0t. CULTURE AS SYSTEM AND PRACTICE Much of the theoretical writing on culture during the past ten years has assumed that a concept of culture as a system of symbols and meanings is at odds with a concept of culture as practice. System and practice approaches have seemed incompatible, I think, because the most prominent practitioners of the culture-as-systemof-meanings approach effectively marginalized consideration of culture-as-practice-if they didn't preclude it altogether. This can be seen in the work of both Clifford Geertz and David Schneider. Geertz's analyses usually begin auspiciously enough, in that he frequently explicates cultural systems in order to resolve a puzzle arising from concrete practices-a state funeral, trances, a royal procession, cockfights. But it usually turns out that the issues of practice are principally a means of moving the essay to the goal of specifying in a synchronic form the coherence that underlies the exotic cultural practices in question. And while Geertz marginalized questions of practice, Schneider, in a kind of reductioadabsurdum,explicitly excluded them, arguing that the particular task of anthropology in the academic division of labor was to study "culture as a system of symbols and meanings in its own right and with reference to its own structure" and leaving to others-sociologists, historians, political scientists, or economists-the question of how social action was structured." A "cultural account," for Schneider, should be limited to specifying the relations among symbols in a given domain of meaning-which he tended to render unproblematically as known and accepted by all members of the society and as possessing a hi~hh· determinate formal logic." Nor is the work of Cecrtz and Schneider unusual in its marginalization of practice. As critics such as James Clifford have arTlie Concept's) afCulture gued, conventional modes of writing in cultural anthropology typically smuggle highly debatable assumptions into ethnographic accounts-for example, that cultural meanings are normally shared, fixed, bounded, and deeply felt. To Clifford's critique of ethnographic rhetoric, I would add a critique of ethnographic method. Anthropologists working with a conception of culture-as-system have tended to focus on clusters of symbols and meanings that can be shown to have a high degree of coherence or systematicity-those of American kinship or Balinese cockfighting, for instance-and to present their accounts of these clusters as examples of what the interpretation of culture in general entails. This practice results in what sociologists would call sampling on the dependent variable. That is, anthropologists who belong to this school tend to select symbols and meanings that cluster neatly into coherent systems and pass over those that are relatively fragmented or incoherent, thus confirming the hypothesis that symbols and meanings indeed form tightly coherent systems. Given some of these problems in the work of the culture-assystem school, the recent turn to a concept of culture-as-practice has been both understandable and fruitful-it has effectively highlighted many of the earlier school's shortcomings and made up some of its most glaring analytic deficits. Yet the presumption that a concept of culture as a system of symbols and meanings is at odds with a concept of culture as practice seems to me perverse. System and practice are complementary concepts: each presupposes the other. Toengage in cultural practice means to utilize existing cultural symbols to accomplish some end. The employment of a symbol can be expected to accomplish a particular goal only because the symbols have more or less determinate meanings-meanings specified by their systematically structured relations to other symbols. Hence practice implies system. But it is equally true that the system has no existence apart from the succession of practices that instantiate, reproduce. or-most interestingly-transform it. Hence system implies practice." System and practice constitute an indissoluble duality or dialectic: the important theoretical question is thus not whether culture should be conceptualized as practice or as a system of symbols and meanings, but how to conceptualize the articulation of system and practice. 48 49William H. Scwcll, Jr. TJlE AUTONOMY OF CULTURE Let me begin this task by stating some assumptions about practice. I assume that human practice, in all social contexts or institutional spheres, is structured simultaneously both by meanings and by other aspects of the environment in which they occur-by, for example, power relations or spatiality or resource distributions. Culture is neither a particular kind of practice nor practice that takes place in a particular social location. It is, rather, the semiotic dimension of human social practice in general. I further assume that these dimensions of practice mutually shape and constrain each other but also that they are relatively autonomous from each other.F TIle autonomy of the cultural dimension of practice can also be understood by thinking about culture as a system. TIle cultural dimension of practice is autonomous from other dimensions of practice in two senses. First, culture has a semiotic structuring principle that is different from the political, economic, or geographical structuring principles that also inform practice. Hence, even if an action were almost entirely determined by, say, overwhelming disparities in economic resources, those disparities would still have to be rendered meaningful in action according to a semiotic logic-that is, in language or in some other form of symbols. For example, an impoverished worker facing the only manufacturer seeking laborers in that district will have no choice but to accept the offer. Yetin accepting the offer she or he is not simply submitting to the employer but entering into a culturally defined relation as a wageworker. Second, the cultural dimension is also autonomous in the sense that the meanings that make it up-although influenced by the context in which they are employed-are shaped and reshaped by a multitude of other contexts. The meaning of a symbol always transcends any particular context, because the symbol is freighted with its usages in a multitude of other instances of social practice. Thus, our worker enters into a relationship of "wageworker" that carries certain recognized mcanings-of deference, but also of independence from the employer and perhaps of solidarity with other wageworkers. These meanings are carried over from the other contexts in which the meaning of wage work is determined-not only from other instances of hirings but from statutes, legal arguments, strikes, socialist tracts, and economic treatises. They enter importantly into The Concepits) ojCII!tII re defining the local possibilities of action, in this case perhaps granting the worker greater power to resist the employer than the local circumstances alone would have dictated. To understand fully the significance of this second sort of autonamy, it is important to note that the network of semiotic relations that make up culture is not isomorphic with the network of economic, political, geographical, social, or demographic relations that make up what we usually call a "society." A given symbol-mother, red, polyester, liberty, wage labor, or dirt-is likely to show up not only in many different locations in a particular institutional domain (motherhood in millions of families) but in a variety of different institutional domains as well (welfare mothers as a potent political symbol, the mother tongue in linguistic quarrels, the Mother of God in the Catholic Church). Culture may be thought of as a network of semiotic relations cast across society, a network with a different shape and different spatiality than institutional, or economic, or political networks." The meaning of a symbol in a given context may therefore be subject to redefinition by dynamics entirely foreign to that institutional domain orspatial location: thus, for example, in the 1950S a particular political meaning of the symbol "red" became so overpowering that the Cincinnati Reds baseball team felt the need to change its name to "the Redlegs." This fact is what makes it possible-indeed virtually guarantees-that the cultural dimension of practice will have a certain autonomy from its other dimensions. If culture has a distinct semiotic logic, then by implication it must in some sense be coherent. But it is important not to exaggerate or misspecify the coherence of symbol systems. I assume the COherence; of a cultural system to be semiotic in a roughly Saussurian sense: that is, that the meaning of a sign or symbol is a function of its network of oppositions to or distinctions from other signs in the system. This implies that users of culture will form a semiotic community-in the] sense that they will recognize the same set of oppositions and therefore be capable of engaging in mutually meaningful symbolic action. To use the ubiquitous linguistic analogy, they will be capable of using the "grammar" of the semiotic system to make understandable "utterances." It should be noted, however, that this conception actually implies only a quite minimal cultural coherence-one might call it a thin coherence. The fact that members of a semiotic community recognize a 51Willia1ll H. Sciccll, Jr.5° given set of symbolic oppositions does not determine what sort of statements or actions they will construct on the basis of their semiotic competence. Nor does it mean that they form a community in any fuller sense. They need not ilgree in their moral or emotional evaluations of given symbols. The semiotic field they share may be recognized and used by groups and individuals locked in fierce enmity rather than bound by solidarity, or by people who feel relative indifference toward each other. The posited existence of cultural coherence says nothing about whether semiotic fields are big or small, shallow or Jeep, encompassing?r specialized. It simply requires that if meaning is to exist at all, there must be systematic relations among ( signs and a group of people who recognize those relations. That this Saussurian conception implies only a thin cultural coherence seems consonant with certain deconstructionist arguments. The entire thrust of deconstruction has been to reveal the instability of linguistic meaning. It has located this instability in the signifying mechanism of language itself-s-claiming that because the meaning of a linguistic sign always depends on a contrast with what the sign is opposed to or different from, language is inevitably haunted by the traces of the very terms it excludes. Consequently, the meaning of a text or an uttcrance can never be fixed; attempts to secure meaning can only defer, never exclude, a plethora of alternative or opposed interpretations. Cultural analysts who-like me-wish to argue that cultural systerns are powerfully constraining have often drawn back from deconstructionist arguments in horror. I think this is a major mistake; indeed, I would maintain that a broadly deconstructionist understanding of meaning is essential for anyone attempting to theorize cultural change. Deconstruction does not deny the possibility of coherence. Rather, it assumes that the coherence inherent in a system of symbols is thin in the sense I have described: it demonstrates over and over that what are taken as the certainties or truths of texts or discourses are in fact disputable and unstable. This seems entirely compatible with a practice perspective on culture. It assumes that symbol systems have a (Saussurian) logic but that this logic is openended, not closed. And it strongly implies that when a given symbol S\'SIC111 is taken by its users to be unambiguous and highly constraining, these qualities cannot be accounted for by their semiotic qualil ios alone but must result from the WilY their semiotic structures Tile Conceptis) o!Cllfture are interlocked in practice with other structures-economic, political, social, spatinl, and so on.> Thus far in this section I have mainly been considering culture as system. But what I have said has implications for how we might conceptualize culture as practice. First, the conception of culture as semiotic implies a particular notion of cultural practice. To engage in cultural practice is to make use of a semiotic code to do something in the world. People who are members of a semiotic community are capable not only of recognizing statements made in a semiotic code (as I have pointed out above) but of using the code as well, of putting it into practice. To use a code means to attach abstractly available symbols to concrete things or circumstances and thereby to posi t something about them. I would also argue that to be able to use a code means more than being able to apply it mechanically in stereotyped situations-it also means having the ability to elaborate it, to modify or adapt its rules to novel circumstances. What things in the world areis never fully determined by the symbolic net we throw over them-this also depends on their preexisting physical characteristics, the spatial relations in which they occur,1 the relations of power with which they are invested, their economic value, and, of course, the different symbolic meanings that may have been attributed to them by other actors. The world is recalcitrant to our predications of meaning. Hence, as Marshall Sahlins has pointed out, every act of symbolic attribution puts the symbols at risk, ma~es it possible that the meanings of the symbols will be inflected or transformed by the uncertain consequences of practice. Usually, such at, tributions result in only tiny inflections of the meaning of symbols. But on some occasions-for example, when Hawaiian chiefs used the category of tabu to enforce their monopoly on trade with Western merchants-novel attributions can have the result of transforming the meaning of a symbol in historically crucial ways."' Part of what gives cultural practice its potency is the ability of actors to play on the multiple meanings of symbols-thereby redefining situations in ways that they believe will favor their purposes. Creative cultural action commonly entails the purposeful or spontaneous importation of meanings from one social location or context to another. I have recently worked on a telling example of the importation of meaning. The men and women who captured the Bastille in July of 1789 were unquestionably characterizable as "the 52 53Wilfiillll H. Scit'cll, fl'. people" in the common sense of "the mob" or the "urban poor." But Parisian radicals and members of the french National Assembly played on the ambiguity of the term to cast those who took the Bastille also as a concrete instance of the abstract category of "the people" who were said to be sovereign in radical political theory. Importing the association between the people and sovereignty from the context of political theory into that of urban crowd violence had the not inconsequential effect of ushering the modern concept of revolution into the world." CULTURES AS DISTINCT WORLDS OF MEANING Up to now, I have been considering culture only in its singular and abstract sense-as a realm of social life defined in contrast to some other noncultural realm or realms. My main points may be summarized as follows: culture, I have argued, should be understood as a dialectic of system and practice, as a dimension of social life autonomous from other such dimensions both in its logic and in its spatial configuration, and as a system of symbols possessing a(real but thin cohercnce)h