An Awkward Relationship: The Case of Feminism and Anthropology Author(s): Marilyn Strathern Source: Signs, Vol. 12, No. 2, Reconstructing the Academy (Winter, 1987), pp. 276-292 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3173986 Accessed: 04/08/2009 05:29 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Signs. http://www.jstor.org AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 AN AWKWARD RELATIONSHIP: THECASEOF FEMINISM AND ANTHROPOLOGY MARILYN STRATHERN Feminist scholarship offers the promise of a common ground between disciplines. Yet this very promise also raisesquestions aboutthe impact of feminist theory on mainstreamdisciplinarydevelopment. Indeed, the one idea-the desirability of establishing autonomous women's studies centers-invariably recalls the other-the desirability of revolutionizing mainstreamestablishments-a pairofpropositionswhich encapsulatesthe ideational divide between autonomy and integration that gives feminist theories their politicaledge. The factthatfeminist scholarshipworksacross disciplines means it cannot be parallelwith them, and this is awkwardin relation to the idea that feminist insights might modifyworkin any single This article is based on a lecture given in the series, Changing Paradigms:The Impactof Feminist Theory upon the World of Scholarship, at the Research Center for Women's Studies, Adelaide, Australia, July 1984. I thank Susan Margarey for her invitation and hospitality, and for thus drawing my attention to the issues of paradigms. The lecture was published in Australian Feminist StudiesJournal 1 (December 1985):1-25. I had spoken on similarthemes atthe Department ofAnthropology,University ofCalifornia,Berkeley, andat the History of Consciousness Unit, SantaCruz, and thankcolleagues at both places fortheir comments. Inspiration also came from the Research Group on Gender Relations in the Southwest Pacificat the AustralianNational University. The journal'sreaderswill recognize ideas of theirs, for which I am most grateful. [Signs:Journal of Women in Culture and Society 1987, vol. 12, no. 2] ? 1987 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/87/1202-0007$01.00 276276276276276276276276276 Winter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNS discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. discipline, for instance, anthropology. For its impact to be registered on mainstreamtheorizing, feminist scholarshipwould have to be construedas an isomorphic sister "discipline"fromwhich ideas and concepts could be borrowed. Any conceptualization of the relationship between feminism and anthropology must account for this awkwardness. Much of the literature on the failureof feminist scholarshipto change disciplines assumes the isomorphism of feminist studies and traditional disciplines, forit is often couched in termsofthe immense taskofparadigm shift. The idea that paradigmscan be shifted suggests two things at once. The underlying assumptions that constitute disciplinarybias in its unreformed state are exposed; at the same time, displacing these with a conscious theoretical frameworkchallenges existing theoretical frameworks. Fundamental premises are thus open to assault. Yet this idea of paradigm shift, so dear to our representations of what we do, turns out to be an inadequate description of our practice. I shall try to show why. Disciplines are distinct both in their subject matters and in their practices. Feminist studies examine new subjects which they can offer to different disciplines: "placingwomen at the center, as subjects of inquiry and as active agents in the gathering of knowledge."' What, then, of differentpractices?Practicesareconstituted by theoreticalframeworks,by conceptual givens and assumptions, and also by the kind of relationship which an investigator establishes with the subject itself. This article explores some ofthe problems thatdisciplinarypracticescanput in the wayof responsiveness to feminist theorizing. It focuses on the investigator'srelationship with his or her subject, a source of particularlyawkwarddissonance between feminist practice and the practice of the discipline I know best, social anthropology. It is perhaps ironic to highlight a dissonance between feminism and anthropology, for anthropology is sometimes singled out for the extent to which it hasbeen affectedby feminist thinking. Certainlyanthropologyhas interests parallel to those of feminist scholarship, but the proximation makes anthropologists'resistance more poignant. Indeed, it maywell be, asone ofthe Signsreadersput it, thatthe dissonanceis actuallyaproductof feminists' andanthropologists'intellectual proximity-that they are, asthe reader suggested, neighbors in tension, neighbors whose similaritiesprovoke them to mutual mockery. I press home the point by considering the dissonance between specific branches of feminist and anthropological theorizing which on the surface appear congenial to one another. Rather than looking at well-established areas of anthropology, I consider an innovative approach that shares common interests with radical feminism. 1Judith Stacey and Barrie Thorne, "The Missing Feminist Revolution in Sociology," Social Problems32, no. 4 (April1985):301-16. I amgratefulto BarrieThorne, fromwhom this article has profited greatly. 277277277277277277277277277 Strathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGY Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). Practitioners of both imagine they might be overthrowing existing paradigms, and one might, in turn, expect "radical"anthropologyto drawon its feminist counterpart. This does not seem to have happened. Their resistance to one anotherwill throwlight on the differencebetween "feminism" and "anthropology"as such. Anthropology: Successful or unsuccessful? The affinity between feminist and anthropological thought is central in Judith Stacey and BarrieThorne's account of the missing feminist revolution in sociology. Anthropology, they state, joins history and literature as the fields in which the most impressive feminist conceptual shifts have occurred. The impressive gains of anthropologycan be attributed to the "significant female imprint on the anthropological pavements from the discipline's earliest days," to the centrality of kinship and gender in traditional anthropological analysis, and to a holistic perspective that accepts gender as a pervasive principle of social organization.2 In many ways ideas generated by feminist inquiry have received a ready response in mainstreamsocialanthropologists'descriptions of other societies. No one any longer can talkunselfconsciously about the position of women. It is no longer possible to assume that women are to be measured by the status they hold relative to another or relegated to a chapter dealing with marriage and the family. The study of gender has become a field in its own right. Most majorareas of anthropology were rapidlycolonized by such ideas during the enormous growthof interest in feminism in the 1970s, creating the subdiscipline of feminist anthropology. The early questions asked by feminist anthropology-What is the place of ideology in collective representations?How do systems of inequality arise?Are analyticcategories such as "domestic"and "political"useful? and, How are concepts of personhood constituted?-remain at the forefrontofits concerns. Moreover, the discipline provides materialsforpartof the feminist enterprise, namely, the scrutiny of Western constructs. Anthropologists have investigated Western biological idioms; have stressed thatwhat happens to women cannotbe comprehended unless we look at what happens to men and women, and that what happens in that realm cannot be comprehended without attention to the overall social system; and continue to provide glimpses into other worlds, into different 2 StaceyandThorne, 303. See alsoCarolMacCormack,"Anthropology-a Discipline with a Legacy," in Men'sStudies Modified, ed. Dale Spender (New York:PergamonPress, 1981), 99-110. Judith Shapiro, however, includes anthropology in her castigation of the social sciences, which "haveyet to come to terms with gender as a socialfact"("Anthropologyand the Study of Gender," in A Feminist Perspective in the Academy, ed. E. Langland and W. Gove [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983], 110-29, esp. 112). 278278278278278278278278278 Winter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNS forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. forms of oppression and freedom. Anthropologysupplies a range of crosscultural data that, to borrow a phrase, are good to think with. The discipline thus appearsto offeranunparalleledpositionfromwhich to scrutinize Western assumptions, enlarging the scope of feminist enterprise by reminding us of the conditions under which women live elsewhere. Yet, in the early 1970s, specificfeminist interest entered anthropology in the form of stinging attackson the discipline's male bias. This was a clear signal that anthropologistscould not affordto be complacent. Simply having had a "place" somewhere for women in their accounts was not enough; they could well be replicating male evaluations of women in the societies they studied. Thisfeminist critique ofbiasquicklyfound its mark. Afterall, feminists were askingthe kindsof questions about ideologies and models that anthropologists recognized. In short, they gave excellent anthropological advice.3 Stacey and Thorne perceive such innovationsin anthropologythrough the formula of paradigm shift. To them, feminist gains in anthropology have shifted paradigmsin two senses: existingconceptualframeworkshave been challenged, and the transformationhas been accepted by others in the discipline. Thus "ofall the disciplines, feminist anthropologyhas been the most successful in both of these dimensions."4 Anthropology is similarly, though less optimistically, singled out in Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove's collection of essays on feminist perspectives in the academy.5 By comparison with the state of affairsin several disciplines, they conclude that anthropologists have long been sensitive to differences in male and female behavior, but they leave it at that. Whereas Stacey and Thorne see anthropology6as accomplishing a double paradigm shift, Langlandand Gove's more pessimistic reflections see the major shift still to come. However, these authors both take a transformationof frameworksas the criterion for success. Langlandand Gove speakof the resistance documented in their collections: the scholars agree that while a "feminist perspective has begun to affect the shape of what is known-and knowable-in their respective 3 See Jane MonnigAtkinson, "Anthropology(Review Essay),"Signs:Journal ofWomenin Culture and Society 8, no. 2 (Winter 1982):236-58, esp. 238. Ironically, Edwin Ardener's paper on the problem of women was written to elucidate certain features of model building and, in retrospect, has become a contribution to feminist literature; see Edwin Ardener, "Belief and the Problem of Women," in The Interpretation of Ritual, ed. Jean La Fontaine (London: Tavistock Publications, 1972). 4 Stacey and Thorne, 302. 5Elizabeth Langland and Walter Gove, A Feminist Perspective in the Academy: The Difference It Makes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983; first published by the Society for Values in Higher Education and Vanderbilt University, 1981). 61refer to social/culturalanthropology. A moderate case forphysical anthropologyis put by Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, "Body, Bias, and Behavior:A ComparativeAnalysis of ReasoninginTwoAreasofBiologicalScience," Signs9, no. 2 (Winter 1983):206-27, esp. 226. 279279279279279279279279279 Stathen / ANTHROPOLOGYStathen / ANTHROPOLOGYStathen / ANTHROPOLOGYStathen / ANTHROPOLOGYStathen / ANTHROPOLOGYStathen / ANTHROPOLOGYStathen / ANTHROPOLOGYStathen / ANTHROPOLOGYStathen / ANTHROPOLOGY disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. disciplines, perhaps the more urgent note in each essay is the failure of women's studies to altercollege anduniversitycurricula.Paperafterpaper concludes that, while the potential power to transformthe discipline is great, women's studies has not yet significantly unleashed that power."7 They echo an overview of women's studies that refers to the "massive resistance against which feminist scholarsstruggle."8Langlandand Gove ask about the cause of the failure. Their answer is in terms of a paradigm model (though this is not a phrase they use): "Women'sstudies has had so little impact on traditional bodies of knowledge because it challenges deeply held, often sacred beliefs .... [It] challenges vested interests; it uproots perspectives which are familiar, and, because familiar, comfortable .... [For] women's studies is not an additionalknowledge merely to be tacked on to the curriculum. It is, instead, a body of knowledge that is perspective transforming and should therefore transformthe existing curriculum from within and revise received notions of what constitutes an 'objective' or 'normative'perspective."9In other words, feminist analyses have not substantiallyinfluenced traditionalcurriculabecause such analyses challenge fundamental disciplinary frameworks. As faras the impact of feminist thought on anthropologyis concerned, where would one place the resistance? Can one in fact see it in terms of challenge and counter-challenge over paradigms? Socialanthropologyis in manyways an open discipline. Faced with an arrayof social and culturalsystems, its practitionerstend to grabfora tool kit, in JamesClifford'sphrase(see n. 30), which containssuchconstructsas can be turned to analytical utility. Specializations proliferate-regional ethnography, economics and politics, legal theory-as do frameworksMarxism, structuralism, symbolic anthropology. This tolerance made room for the study of gender and for feminist ideas. Yet a milieu of tolerance has also reduced feminist scholarshipto just another approach, one way among many into the data. Consequently, a declared interest in putting women back on the map encourages theoretical containment. If feminist scholarshipis seen as the study of women or of gender, its subject can be taken as something less than "society." Feminist anthropology is thus tolerated as a specialty that can be absorbedwithout challenge to the whole. Within anthropology few names are associated with an exclusively feminist position. Rather, feminist anthropologyis tied to a general cate- 7 Langland and Gove, 2. 8 MarilynBoxer, "ForandAboutWomen:TheTheoryandPracticeofWomen's Studies in the United States," in Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology, ed. Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo, and BarbaraGelpi (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1982), 260. 9 Langland and Gove, 3-4. 280280280280280280280280280 Winter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNS gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. gory, to "women"asits practitioners,aswell asits subjectmatter. 0Clearly it is the intention ofmanyfeminist scholarsto restorewomen to view. Butit is unfortunate that their concerns can be concretized in this way. Where feminist anthropologists see themselves as taking on the whole of the discipline, they are met with a tendency to section off gender analysis or women's studies from the rest of anthropology. Perhaps, as Langlandand Gove would argue, this is a reaction to threat. Feminist-inspired anthropologists raising questions about male bias could be regardedas challenging the foundation of the subject, with its theoretical emphasis on group structures, on systems of authority, and on rules and norms, and with its assumptions about the description of total systems. Ironically, however, where these concepts have most powerfully come under scrutiny-and "groups,""rules," and "norms"have hardly survived the last decade-it has been in response to internal criticism that has had little to do with feminist theory. Meanwhile, social anthropology still continues to know itself as the study of social behavior or society in terms of systems and collective representations. Ifthese constitute aparadigm,then it is largely intact. Is this in fact a process of challenge and counter-challenge? Does feminist theory present a profoundthreat to core paradigms?And has the threatbeen ingeniously deflected by the restofthe anthropologicalpopulation, assuming it is just "aboutwomen"? Both the idea of challenge and counter-challenge, and anthropology'sother face, its openness to feminist ideas, invite one to think in terms of paradigms. Indeed, Stacey and Thorne characterize the fields in which feminist thinking has had most headway as ones with "strong traditions of interpretive understanding," thatis, ones thatarereflexive andself-critical." Here the conclusion would seem to be that those disciplines most aware of the paradigmaticbases upon which they proceed will be most open to paradigm shift. This argument, however, contains an interesting flaw. The flaw is made visible by the invocation of Thomas Kuhn'swork on paradigms in scientific theory. Without such a reminder one might get away with a commonsense understanding of paradigmsas "basicconceptual frameworksand orienting assumptions of a body of knowledge."12 Yet one significant feature of the Kuhnian paradigmis that the scientists he studied become awareofparadigmshiftonly afterthe fact.The whole point 10See Judith Shapiro, "Cross-culturalPerspectives on Sexual Differentiation,"in Human Sexuality:A Comparative and Developmental Perspective, ed. H. Katchadourian(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1979). "l Stacey and Thorne (n. 1 above), 309. 12Ibid., 302; Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Langland and Gove do not cite Kuhn, though their terminology strongly suggests that they are familiarwith his work. 281281281281281281281281281 Strathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGY is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. is thatthey do not aimto shiftparadigms-they aimto accountforthingsby what they know. The twin ideas ofparadigmsandthe possibility of shifting them remain powerful ones. These ideas belong to the way innovative scholars represent themselves. They are part of the way they talk about what they do. The image of perspective transformationbelongs to the rhetoric of radicalism-and requires explanationas partof that rhetoric.13 The rhetoric of paradigm shifting Paradigmenters the vocabularyof the social sciences (andhumanities) to referto aconstructed model. One mayenvisage new paradigms"invented" or an alternate paradigm"emerging."'4The idea of overturningparadigms is apopularmetaphorforthe perceived challenge andcounter-challenge in the relationship between feminist scholarshipand established disciplines. It is the received radicalview that people will defend their present paradigms because it is too uncomfortableor threatening to give up what one has. In her survey on women's studies, MarilynBoxer observes, "Justas manyfeminists found thatthe goalsofthe women's movement could notbe fulfilled by the 'add-women-and-stirmethod,' so women's studies scholars discovered that academic fields could not be cured of sexism simply by accretion."'5Initial compensatory scholarship led to the realization that only radical reconstruction would suffice. Many scholars have found an explanationin Kuhn'stheory of scientific revolutions. Kuhn'sformulations aretakenasjust asapplicableto the socialsciences asthey areto the natural sciences for which he developed them. I suggest that they are less applicable than appears at first sight. I give one example. Elizabeth Janewayfollows Kuhn'sformulationsin detail to show that they provide apowerful analogyforthe investigation of sex stereotypes.16 He defined aparadigmasanimplicitbody ofintertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criticism. Change is first evaluated, then registered as an anomalythe pressure of anomalies eventually forcing a new normative model. Janeway argues that male representations of female sexuality provide patterns that fit into the accepted structure of behavior, beliefs that provide a source of permissible metaphorsthroughwhich people think about themselves, standards for behavior, and exemplars learned from the 13See Longino and Doell; Donna Haraway, "In the Beginning Was the Word: The Genesis of Biological Theory," Signs 6, no. 3 (Spring 1981):469-81. 14See Elizabeth Janeway,"WhoIs Sylvia?On the Lossof SexualParadigms,"Signs5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):573-89, esp. 588; and Ethel Spector Person, "Sexualityas the Mainstayof Identity: Psychoanalytic Perspectives," Signs 5, no. 4 (Summer 1980):605-30, esp. 613. 15 Boxer, 258. 16 Janeway. 282282282282282282282282282 Winter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNS anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. anonymous pressure of ascriptive social mythology. Beliefs about female sexuality also act like Kuhnianparadigmsin their response to anomalies. Over time, anomalies force paradigmsinto a different position; instead of being takenforgranted,they become idealspreached about. Indeed, she is concerned to press the point that for some, male sexual stereotypes never fitted. Women could never share fully in them, since they cannot fit themselves into expectations of male normalcy. Paradigms in her view establish the rules of normalcy. Yet, what do we do with the internal contradictions that Janeway's "paradigms"also seem to entail? The very constructionof normalcyalong exclusive male lines, forinstance, invites questions about the place of men and women in relation to its definition of what is normal. Janewaywrites, "The shared beliefs and values expressed by our 'paradigms'of female sexuality are not, in fact, sharedfully by the women who have had to take them as models."'71would suggest that the factthey are not sharedcomes less from a failure of a paradigm to accommodate reality than from the structure of an ideology which, in speaking to certain social interests, also reproduces others and thus promotes contradictory propositions. It is important, then, to look at the manner in which so-called paradigmsare shared. SandraCoyner advises women's studies practitionersto "abandonthe energy-draining and still overwhelmingly unsuccessful effortto transform the established disciplines. Instead they should continue developing the new community of feminist scholars who will eventually discover new paradigms and found a new normative science."18This interesting statement breaks with the assumption that paradigms are like some set of cultural norms; instead, it locates paradigmsin relationto a community of practitioners. The question is whether we are still dealing with paradigms or not. Kuhnhimself claims thathis investigations in naturalscience stemmed from realizing the extent to which social science, by contrast, was characterized by overt disagreement. He professes to be puzzled at the way his notion of paradigm had been adopted in other fields.19Kuhn notes the specific natureofthe communityin naturalscience: there arerelativelyfew competing schools, so thatrevolutions affectuniversalperceptions; a community's members are the onlyjudge of one another;and puzzle solving is anend in itself. Kuhnemphasizes the sharedmeaningsofparadigmswhich both define a scientific community and are defined by it. Of course, scientific communities exist at different levels, but on the whole there will be agreement about the status of their disagreements. Above all, there is 17 Ibid., 575. 18Cited by Boxer, 260. '9 Kuhn (n. 12 above), on the first point, viii; on the second, 208. 283283283283283283283283283 Strathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGY general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual general agreement about scientists' relationship to their subject matter: the world presents them with problems to be solved. These are the characteristicsofaclosed system. Revolution serves only to close the system again: successive paradigmsreplace or substitute for one another. Overt competition between paradigmsis short-livedbecause the proponents of the new paradigmclaim they have solved the problems thatput the old one in crisis. Yetthis hardlyfitsthe present case offeminist scholarship, insofaras it has an interest in sustainingantagonismbetween "paradigms."Here it is the very championing of a new "paradigm"that makesthe old one problematic. Indeed, it is in feminists'overt interests to take a conflict view of their social context. If so, its explicit conceptual frameworkscannot be regarded as paradigms. Competitive premises Talking about paradigms is not the same as using them. The metaphor suggests the immovabilityof massivefoundationsandthe herculean taskit would be to dislodge them. Yet when we are dealing with social scientists who constantly overturntheir own theories andconstructexplicit histories of internal revolution, I do not think the key to resistance is feminism's challenge to intellectual frameworks, let alone "paradigms."I wish to accountforthe awkwardnessinthe relationshipbetween anthropologyand feminism, and the continuing resistance thatfeminist scholarshipencounters, in different terms. Talkabout "paradigms"belongs to the conscious effortto establish anew subject matter. Whatcannotbe so self-consciously shifted, I shall argue, is the nature of investigators' relationship to their subject matter that particularscholarlypractices create. We must look to the social constitution of both feminist and anthropologicalpractice. Neither feminist scholarship nor social anthropology is closed in the Kuhniansense. Thus there is no one anthropology;its practitionersrange fromdeterminists to relativists, fromthose interested in power relationsto those who give primacyto culturalmodels, fromthe politicaleconomists to the hermeneuticists. Manyof these positions correspond to philosophical ones or have counterpartsin historyorliterarycriticism. When anthropologists call themselves poststructuralists,they cannotescape contemporary literarytraditionsany more than they ever could claim a monopoly on the concept of structuralism.It should be no surprise, then, that smallas it is, the field offeminist anthropologyis based on divisions. Socialanthropological studies of women persistently divide into two camps over whether or not sexual asymmetry is universal. One side argues that Western constructs blind us from seeing egalitarianismin unfamiliarcontexts and that we encounter hierarchicalrelations only in the historicalcontext of privatized ownership. The other side argues that we should look for sexual 284284284284284284284284284 Winter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNS inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. inequality in all its forms, for sexual difference everywhere contributes to socially constituted differences. Diane Bell has called these "evolutionist" and "universalist"positions;they echo established strategies in the anthropological handling of cross-cultural data.20 Anyone overviewing feminist theory alsohasto accommodateits explicitly self-differentiated positions. Labels have a political flavor: liberal/ radical/Marxist-socialist.The political vantage points provide a model for the differentiationof feminist vantagepoints, which againreplicate potential intellectual divisions within Western society at large. Indeed, it may look as though there is an impossible arrayof theoretical positions within feminist debate: "Here we are speaking in many voices."2 Yet it is a phenomenon offeminism thatthe positions areheld explicitlyin relationto one another. Through the vast amount of internal criticism and countercriticism, the voices depend on one another'spresence. It need hardlybe instanced that Marxist-socialistfeminism places itself in relation to both liberaland radicalfeminism and is constantlycommenting on the fact. The arguments are never dispatched. In other words, no one viewpoint is self-reproductive: feminist "theory"is created dialogically, in the sense that all the positions in the debate constitute its base. The pluralism that characterizes both anthropology and feminist scholarshipwould seem to have them touch mutualground at several points. Andhere is the contrast with natural science: not simply that within such scholarly practice one findsdiverse "schools"(alsotrue in science) but alsothattheir premises are by their nature constructed competitively in relation to one another. Kuhn characterized the relationship of scientific scholarsto their subject matter as one of problem solving. The naturalworld is conceived as made up of different things, ultimately related through sets of "laws" which by "naturallogic"22cannot be in conflict. The problem is how to specify these laws. Paradigmsprovide rules for registering the nature of the problem and what its solution would look like. In the social sciences, however, the differences between the theoretical positions I have been talkingabout correspond to the formationof different social interests. The social world is conceived as made up of persons who are basically similar but divided between themselves by interests that may indeed conflict; more than that, "social logic" allows contradictoryviewpoints. Scholarly 20Diane Bell, Daughters of the Dreaming (Melbourne:McPhee Gribble/George Allen & Unwin, 1984), 245-46. 21 Haraway (n. 13 above), 481; see also Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980);Hester Eisenstein, Contemporary Feminist Thought (Sydney: Unwin Paperbacks, 1984);Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981),esp. xix;JanetSayers, BiologicalPolitics:FeministandAnti-Feminist Perspectives (London: Tavistock Publications, 1982). 22Compare T. M. S. Evens, "Mind, Logic and the Efficacyof the Nuer Incest Prohibition," Man, n.s., 18 (1983): 111-33. 285285285285285285285285285 Strathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGY practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith practice concerned with the constitution of this social world internally replicates this differentiation. It would be pointless to seek a homogenization or reconciliation of all points of view; there can be, in this sense, no common worldview. What is seen to constitute the socialworld, rather, is the natureofthe relationshipsbetween differentviews fromdifferentsocial positions. The anthropologist does not wish to assimilate the characterof other systems to his or her own. The essence of the comparative method is to make sense of differences, not collapse them. Feminist theory also has an interest in difference-in constantly bringing to mind the "difference it makes" to consider things from a perspective that includes women's interests. Insofar as men's and women's interests are opposed, perpetual effortmust bring this to attention. Again,homogenization makesno sense. Feminism's and anthropology'sconcerns in promoting difference would seem to be further grounds for mutual convergence. So why the resist- ance? The answer cannot lie in "paradigms,"first, because the different theoretical positions occupied in the social sciences are not analogous to the paradigms of Kuhnian science. They are based on overt conflict between competitive conceptual frameworks which cannot be reduced to single positions and, second, because theoretical positions, in anthropology at least, are in fact overturned and displaced very easily-radicalisms abound. It may be objected that such positions are not, then, really of paradigmaticstatus, andwe should lookfordeeper paradigms.Yetto do so would be easier from within anthropology:for instance, it is encounters with alien social and cultural systems that allow one to scrutinize the subject/object dichotomy or commodity notions that informWestern concepts of personhood and identity. From the anthropologicalpoint of view, much feminist thinking participates in such constructs, embodying ethnocentric commentary upon the world. Third, the awkward relationship between feminism and anthropologyis lived most dramaticallyin the tension experienced by those who practice feminist anthropology. They are caughtbetween structures:the scholaris facedwith two different ways of relating to her or his subject matter. The tension must be kept going; there can be no relief in substituting the one for the other. Neighbors in tension For the tension between feminist scholarship and anthropology, I have used the term "awkward,"to suggest a doorstep hesitation rather than barricades. Each in a sense mocks the other, because each so nearly achieves what the other aims for as an ideal relation with the world. There is, in anthropologicalinquiry, a long traditionof breakingwith 286286286286286286286286286 Winter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNS the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. the past, so that theoretical generations tend to be short-lived. A recent heir to this constant radicalizationare innovations interesting in the present context for the weight placed on the interpretation of experience. Experience is also an explicit topic of feminist inquiry. The well-argued radicalview is that feminist theory is "experiential,"23in the sense that its firststep is consciousness raising. In transmutedform, a number offeminist anthropologists emphasize the significance of experience. RaynaRapp reported in her 1979 review of anthropology the "searchfor analysis of more finely delineated female experience";she laternotes interest in "the lived body"-women's self-concepts as mediated through perceptions of their bodies.24Nancy Scheper-Hughes addresses a feminist anthropology that explores "the nature of the self" in the fieldworksituation:ethnography as "intellectual autobiography."25Yet the focus on similar issues in general ethnographicwritinghasproceeded asaquite independent radical development, without regardforthe feminist contribution.The anthropologist's aim is to grasp"livedexperience" throughperceptions ofthe body;26 "a new anthropology of ritual experience" is heralded in a collection of essays on initiation rites.27Feminist interest in these matterswould not be challenging "paradigms"that are not alreadyunder challenge fromwithin the anthropology. I think this is because "experience"is not the common meeting ground it appears to be, and my focus on it will be a focus on the awkwardness between anthropology and feminist scholarship as such. I briefly contrast the way the idea of experience is used in nonanthropological feminist discourse and in nonfeminist anthropologicaldiscourse. In each case it is developed as a weapon against orthodoxy. Feminist scholarshipsees itself aschallenging stereotypes that misrepresent women's experiences. Women's experience maybe set againstmale ideology, including academic theory building, which appropriatesspeech andimage in the interests ofpatriarchy.These arethe imagesofsexualityof which Janeway talked-women being made to feel in certain ways about themselves, asthough thatthinkingcould be done forthem. Closely tied to 23 Nannerl Keohane, Michelle Rosaldo,and BarbaraGelpi, eds., "Foreword"to Feminist Theory: A Critique of Ideology (n. 8 above), vii; also Cheri Register, "LiteraryCriticism (Review Essay)," Signs 6, no. 2 (Winter 1980):268-82, esp. 269. StaceyandThorne note that feminist theorists "arereconsidering the relationshipbetween knowerandknownto develop amethod ofinquirythatwill preserve the presence ofthe subjectasanactorandexperiencer," and stress their affinityto others who contribute to hermeneutic and neo-Marxistcritiques of positivist social science (n. 1 above), 309. 24 Rayna Rapp, "Anthropology(Review Essay)," Signs 4, no. 3 (Spring 1979):497-513, esp. 500 and 503. 25 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, "Introduction: The Problem of Bias in Androcentric and Feminist Anthropology," Women's Studies 10 (1983): 115. 26 Michael Jackson, "Knowledge of the Body," Man, n.s., 18 (1983):327-45. 27 Gilbert Herdt, "Preface"to Rituals of Manhood:Male Initiation in Papua New Guinea (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of CaliforniaPress, 1982), esp. xix. 287287287287287287287287287 Strathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGY the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. the personal, experience cannot but resonate with conditions as they are, even if its meaning has to be brought up to individual consciousness. Experience thus becomes the instrument of a knowledge which cannotbe appropriatedby Others. It can only be shared with like persons. Essential to this view of the feminist task is the need to expose and thereby destroy the authority of other persons to determine feminine experience. The constant rediscovery that women are the Other in men's accountsremindswomen thatthey must see men asthe Otherin relationto themselves. Creating a space forwomen becomes creating a space for the self, and experience becomes an instrument for knowing the self. Necessaryto the construction of the feminist self, then, is a nonfeminist Other.28 The Other is most generallyconceived as"patriarchy,"the institutionsand persons who represent male domination, often simply concretized as "men."Because the goalis to restoreto subjectivityaselfdominatedby the Other, there can be no shared experience with persons who standfor the Other. Within anthropology, the ethnographer'sfocus on experience signals an effort to remain open to people's emotional and personal lives. The problem is that in writing his or her account, the ethnographer must first translate another's experience through his or her own and then render experience in the written word. Contemporary experimentation with biography, narrative, and novel constitutes an explicit response to this.29 Experimentation includes recent self-consciousattempts to let the anthropologists' subjects speak for themselves. As a historian of anthropology, James Clifford describes a new genre of works designed to reproduce multiple authorship. Paul Rabinowtypifies the genre as poststructuralist, an "intercalationof mixed genres of texts and voices."30In allowing the so-called informantto speakinhis orher ownvoice, the resultingethnography replicates the interlocutoryprocess offieldwork,which alwaysrestson collaborationbetween anthropologistand informant.Anthropologistsand their reactions are thus part of the data, rather than being mysterious hidden hands. The anthropologist'sown experiences are the lens through which others of his or her own society may achieve a like understanding. 28See Haraway (n. 13 above); and Genevieve Lloyd, "History of Philosophy and the Critique of Reason," Critical Philosophy 1 (1984):5-23, esp. 14. However, Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), delimit varieties of consciousness, of which consciousness of oneself as the object of another's attention is only one. 29Michael Jackson, Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Michael Young, Magicians of Manumanua:Living Myth in Kalauna (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983). 30Paul Rabinow, "'Facts Area Wordof God':An Essay Review ofJamesClifford'sPerson and Myth:MauriceLeenhardtin the MelanesianWorld,"in Observers Observed:History of Anthropology, ed. G. Stocking(Madison:UniversityofWisconsinPress, 1983), 196-207, esp. 196; also James Clifford, "On Ethnographic Authority," Representations 1 (1983): 118-46. 288288288288288288288288288 Winter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNS These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). These experiences consequently become a vehicle forcross-culturalcommentary, as when Rabinow'spersonal reactions in the field reveal a "cultural self."31 Anthropology here constitutes itself in relation to an Other, vis-a-vis the alien culture/society under study. Its distance and foreignness are deliberately sustained. But the Other is not under attack.On the contrary, the effort is to create a relation with the Other, as in the search for a medium ofexpression thatwill offermutualinterpretation,perhapsvisualized as a common text, or a dialogue. Clifford develops the concept of "discourse"to evoke the structure of a dialogue that retains the distinct multiple voices of its authors yet yields a product that they all to some extent share. Under attack,by contrast, is thatpartof oneself embodied in the traditionto which one is heir. It is claimed that the pretensions of the old anthropologyobliterated the multiple authorshipoffieldworkdataand did not acknowledge the input either of the informantor of the anthropologist's particularexperience. Feminist inquiry suggests that it is possible to discover the self by becoming conscious of oppression from the Other. Thus one may seek to regain a common past which is also one's own. Anthropological inquiry suggests that the self can be consciously used as a vehicle forrepresenting an Other. But this is only possible ifthe self breakswith its own past. These thus emerge as two very different radicalisms. For all their parallel interests, the two practices are differently structured in the way they organize knowledge and draw boundaries, in short, in terms of the social relations that define their scholarly communities. Perhaps the differences could be turned into a dialogue between feminist scholarship and anthropology. But it would be an awkwarddialogue insofaras each has a potential for undermining the other. For both are vulnerable on the ethical grounds they hold to be so important. I construct a hypothetical encounter to make the point. Mockery between neighbors How can feminism be said to mock this style of anthropology?The anthropologist is trying to establish him or herself as an interpreter of experiences. Yet obviously the anthropologist would also admit to being in control of the final text. However much multiple authorship is acknowledged, using people's experiences to make statements about matters of anthropological interest in the end subordinates them to the uses of the discipline. But that does not mean it is a worthless exercise. On the 31 See, e.g., Paul Rabinow, Reflectionson Fieldworkin Morocco(Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress, 1977). 289289289289289289289289289 Strathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGY contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. contrary,and the reasonthe issue of ethics is raised, the plea thatmultiple authorshipis desirable speaksto anideal relationshipwith informants.The ethnographeris anxiousnot simplyto renderthe experience ofothers in his or her own terms, but to preserve their separate dignity. To present a monographas a collaborativeproduction, then, is a metaphorfor an ideal ethical situation in which neither voice is submerged by the Other.32 From a feminist perspective, of course, there can be no collaboration with the Other. This anthropologicalideal is a delusion, overlooking the crucial dimension of different social interests. There can be no parity between the authorship of the anthropologist and the informant; the dialogue must alwaysbe asymmetrical. Whether the prime factorsare the colonial relations between the societies from which both anthropologists and informants come or the use to which the text will be put, the social worlds of anthropologist and informant are different. They have no interests in common to be served by this purportedly common product. Although I have used the case of the innovative ethnographyof experience, ethnography in general draws on values widespread within the discipline. Anthropologicalpracticewould cease if it could not implement in some way or another a working ethic of humanism.33The feminist critique comes from different premises, but that does not prevent its poking fun at anthropological pretensions at their most vulnerable. Indeed, mockery always comes from a different vantage point, so the blow strikes infuriatinglyat a tangent. But feminists come close to displayingan alternative route to what anthropologistshope to achieve in collaborative enterprises. Feminist scholars can claim substantialinterests in common with the people they study. They may be speaking woman to woman, or else have a common ground in understanding systems of domination. How, then, could anthropology possibly mock feminism? The radical feminist approachemphasizes the conscious creation of the self by seeing its difference from the Other. Women have to know the extent to which their lives are molded by patriarchal values. It is an achievement to perceive the gulf, and in turn, an ethical position, forthis is what validates women's commitment to one another. Now, if such feminism mocks the anthropological pretension of creating a product in some ways jointly authored, then anthropologymocksthe pretension thatfeminists can ever reallyachieve thatseparationfromanantitheticalOtherwhich they desire. From a vantage point outside their own culture, anthropologistssee that 32 Rabinowsuggests that it is not authenticity that Leenhardt'scoauthoredtexts claimbut "anethically superiorproductofjoint work"(myitalics),204;see JamesClifford,"Fieldwork, Reciprocity and the Making of Ethnographic Texts: The Example of Maurice Leenhardt," Man, n.s., 15 (1980):518-32; and Young (n. 29 above), 34-35. 33Robert Bellah, "Foreword"to Rabinow (n. 31 above), esp. xii. 290290290290290290290290290 Winter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNSWinter 1987 / SIGNS the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. the very basis for the separation rests on common cultural suppositions about the nature of personhood and of relationships. If women construct subjectivity for themselves, they do so strictly within the sociocultural constraints of their own society. The establishment of self must endorse a worldview shared equally by the Other. Again, these constitute ethical issues over which feminist thinkers concern themselves: silent speech; connivanceandparticipationin oppression; how we set about creating a feminist discourse that rejects domination, when language itself is conceived as an instrument of domination.34 Feminism requires adogmaof separatismasapoliticalinstrument in order to constitute a common cause. Anthropologists mock feminists by almost effortlessly achieving that distance fromtheir own society which feminists create with such anguish. Yet, again, the mockeryalsoglances off, because in fact feminists inhabit their own society, and the discovery that their values are culture bound is irrelevant. Feminists can only operationalize their perspectives if these are held to have some congruence with reality. Thus they do not need to know that "really" they cannot distinguish themselves fromthe oppressive Other;on the contrary,what they need to know are all the ways in which "really"they can and must. If we were to seek in the social sciences ideas comparableto the status that paradigms hold in natural science, it might be helpful to recall that paradigmsin Kuhn'saccount are sharedworldviews thatcome fromdoing science rather than from acquiring rules for doing it. In the natural sciences such worldviews necessarily take the form of intellectual paradigms,that is, models fororganizingknowledge about the world. I have suggested that the conscious theorizings about knowledge that characterize both anthropologicaland feminist thought are not best conceptualized as paradigms. Yet there is a set of views analogous to paradigms regarded by feminists and by anthropologists alike as so fundamental thatneither could proceed without them. Butthese views cannot be open to conscious challenge, because they define the very practice by which each acts. They thus do not appearas "views"at all, but as knowledge of the world. It is a social world and involves the differing relationships that feminists and anthropologistshave constructed toward the Other. Although I dwelt on particularapproaches, the construalsof the Other briefly described here can be generalized to feminism and anthropology overall. These constructionsarefundamental.When broughtinto the open and compared, their proponents cannot possibly challenge each other, for the one is no substitute forthe other. As Kuhnwrites of the proponents of 34See Jean Bethke Elshtain, "Feminist Discourse and Its Discontents: Language, Power and Meaning," in Keohane et al., eds. (n. 8 above), 145. 291291291291291291291291291 Strathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGYStrathern / ANTHROPOLOGY competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester competing scientific paradigms, they practice their trades in different worlds. Indeed, the properly paradigmaticstatus of these two practices is revealed in the extent to which they appear irrelevant to each other and thus offer not challenge but what I have called mockery. Department of Social Anthropology University of Manchester 292292292292292292292292292