Why Feminism and Freedom Both Begin with the Letter F The raison ďetre of politics is freedom, and its field of experience is action. -HANNAH ARENDT JU D GIN G FR o M THE spate of publications declaring the "end of feminism," it would seem that feminism, as a social and political movement, has more or less reached its limit.i For some critics, this end is given in supposedly incontrovertible fact that the discrimination feminism set out to challenge is more or less a thing of the past. In their view, gender equality is a legal fact awaiting its full social realization, which, in accordance with the logic of historical progress, is imminent. For other critics, this is clearly not the case. Changes in law do not automatically result in social changes but require the vigilance of an ongoing political movement. If these same critics declare the end of feminism, then, it is more with a sense of loss than triumph. And perhaps they are right: it is increasingly hard to identify the "movement" in the feminist movement; for feminism, when it is not safely ensconced in the formal institutions of the liberal 1/ democratic state, can incleellQ;;k like a dispersed collection of diverse grassroots struggles that have lost the orientatÍon once provided by its collective subject: "women." Critics who long for the clear sense of direction that they identify as sine qua non of feminist politics like to charge third-wave feminism, especially its poststructuralist variant, with the destruction of the collective subject "women," but their accusation flies in the face of political history. Anyone even slightly acquainted with the history of first- and II second-wave American feminism will immediately recognize that the ori-l\ entation provided by this putatively collective subject was illusory at best. Femin~sn:tA!!§J!bYay.s.been,shnuhrough wit~A~eeil1_t_e!E:~!_~2_nfli~2 about the subject in whose name its equally conflict-ridden social and poHtical aspÍľätions werei:o bé,-äčhiev~d:2:"Tliebtéäthľeis-pacewrth which"meritbers-o(the-e~~liest second-wave feminist groups split off to FEMINISM AND FREEDOM BEGIN WITH F I 3 2 I INTRODUCTION found other groups, only to find members of the new group splitting off to found yet other groups, indicates what we might call a retroactive fantasy about the wholeness of political origins, a fantasy that is by no means unique to feminism.3 Far from united at origin, feminism, like all modern democratic political movements (including the American and French revolutions), was divided from the start, wracked by differences over the causes or form of oppression, disputes over the meaning of liberation, and competing understandings of what democratic ideaIs like freedom and equality and the public realm in which they were to find expression should look like. 4 , Such differences and even deep divisions, visible at particular moments in history, appear se1f-defeating only if we assume that the raison d'hre of a democratic political movement like feminism is foremost the social advancement of the group, that such advancement can only be attained if it is in someone's name, and that this name must be known in advance of the political struggle itself. The most trenchant critics of identity polítics, such as Judith Butler, Ernesto Laclau, and Chantal Mouffe, have strongly argued that politics (including not only a post-Marxist notion of radicai democracy but the more traditional forms of social democratic politics) is indeed possible without such a unified and pregiven subject. Although these criticisms are well taken-especially insofar as they disclose the troubling exclusions that a collective subject like "women" or "workers" given in advance of politics carries with itwhat they do not squarely address is the fraught question of whether the raison d'etre of politics, feminist or any form of democratic politics, is indeed the social advancement of the group in whose name members of a political movement claim to speak. Freedom as a Social Question If it is difficult to imagine the raison d'etre of politics as anything other than the social advancement of a group and its members, that may be because ~te!l.4!oJhiIlkgiRgJitic-sjnterms oJwJ1at Hanl1a!t A:t:~E~!9:l!~"the social question." The social question arises wherever it is assumed th;t-a~šsic-š~CiafweIfare problems such as hunger, inequality of wealth, housing, a living wage, and so on are problems that can be solved by political means.5 For Arendt, the social question-already fatefully her view) posed in the French Revolution---comes to be definitíve ofwhat polítics is with the rise of "the social" in the nineteenth century. Although Arendt is not clear in her definition, the social is a ~nd of enlarged "housekeep!!!g,~ whereby the public/private distinction is dissolved and citizens are situated in a relatively passive relation to the bureaucratic apparatus ofthe welfare state, which becomes the sole addressee ofpolitical claims and responsible for the distribution of goods and the maintenance of life. The assimilation of the political to the social restriets /WM!AAr) . --.--- -------_.---- ---.-------.-------.------__~_ _ _ . - - _ jJ..t{.(/.,<.) political action to an instrumental, means-ends activity that entäIlš·the- '" . micro-and macro-managementors·ocial r~l'!tiQ!!.s. Since "societyaTwäys demaridsofltsmem6e~s1:hat·-they~~t;~ if they were members of one enormous family which has only one opinion and one interest," writes Arendt, the rise of the social is identicai with the rise of conformism and "behaviar," and with the consequent reduction of the possibility of spontaneous action (HC, 39).6 Arendťs account of social conformity and the rise of the social resonates with critiques of modern disciplinary society (such as Michel Foucaulťs), which have strongly influenced the shape of recent feminist theory.7 But Arendt's tendency to define all issues related to the body as dangerous forms of necessity that are best kept private if not hidden and her antipathy toward the "administrative housekeeping" of the modern welfare state have made her a controversial figure both on the progressive Left and in contemporary feminism. Notwithstanding a recent shift in feminist attitudes toward Arendt, which reflect a willingness to consider the potential value of her work for a postidentity politics, :w..h~t stubhomly rem-Eln.UH thLeD-_d._ QtJh('!g~y_i.S.hť!L~ppgrent refqs9~,l}n!h~yJp.:~!~~Il!h_~~!1.tl!ry_!l~s deeply feminized. By the early- to mid-twentieth century, Riley writes, "the-'very word 'women' was imbued in all politicallanguages with domesticity in a broad sense, with a limiting notion of sociality."18 Tracking this development, she argues that the inherited idea of a naturalized femininity in the early- to midnineteenth century was redeployed, by advocates and opponents of women's rights alike, in relation to the emerging idea of the social. redeployment, Riley observes, resulted in a "bland redistribution and dilution of the sexual onto the familial," as well as a dispersal of the "irresistibly sexualized elements of 'women' onto new categories of immiseration and delinquency-which then became sociological problems [that women, in their sociologically defined capacity as citizens, were called upon to solve)."19 Doubly positioned as "both agents and objects of reform in unprecedented ways with the ascent of the social," came to be seen more as a sociological,g_r~~p__~~~_~_p:a!.ti.cu~aren I (i U' FEMINISM ANO FREEDOM BEGIN WITH F I 7 social agenda than as an emer~LIlKPQJ!!.!f.!!LC:,Q.lle~tivl!L'Yith un9.~a!i~:~ J~.eIIlQcr..a!i\:,_cJ.~IIl~_t:l:~:tS.,20 Claims to the political status of citizen increasingly had to be made as claims to a certain sociological status; the claim to political freedom was heard as the claim to participate in the public "social housekeeping" that Arendt so disdained. The entanglement of women and the social, then, has deeply influenced what can be heard as a political demand for freedom. Whatever its problems, the term social feminism-coined by the historian William O'Neil1 to describe the women who were municipal civic reformers, members, settlement house residents, and labor activists-captures the new idiom in which the struggle for American women's political rights after 1900 came to be fought.21 Social feminism, I hasten to qualify the accepted narrative, developed as ~than-a claim to sexual difference, the difference women'woulamäke-Ironly'they--weregränted~~p-Qi!!k~l rights.Wl1äT feri:iiiiistS-fácea'wás nórfiistconveIltioiläľ co;~eptions of----'1"- ,.,-,---", femIninity that had ro be strategically redeployed for political purposes, but a ~igntfk~_I]td#pJ~fS!Il!e.!1:t_()UheJ;?Qlinc:;a,IJ?.Yili~J!ocia1. Within the increasingly all-encompassing framework of the social question, the ear!ier claims to women's full political membership as a good in itself, made by feminists like Susan B. Anthony and Elizabeth Cady Stanton, were seen as selfish and narrow. Indeed, these feminists and their unqualified demand for the right to be participators in ,public affairs came to be seen as "hard-core." For social feminists and, indeed, for anyone who made the case for women's rights on the basis of social utility, be it in terms of difference or equality, the ballotwas not an end in itself but a means to an end: the betterment of society.22 In some sense, the dispJa.c.~Il!.eJ1.iEithe political bľ_~~ social is intrinsie to the history oTdemocratic politicsmore-generally. Far from unique to femillism~theartlcurätíôn-oIpoliticarďemaiiasiii the language of the social is a rhetorical strategy that has been, and continues to be, taken up by many disenfranchised groups (for example, the struggle for the gradex.tension of "manhood suffrage" in nineteenth-century England, for rights of African Americans in the United States, for workers' rights in capitalist economies, and for women's human rights in a global conI'cxt), whose advocates, eager to convince those in power of the rightness of their cause, framed it in the language of social utilitý: Although rhetorkal strategy-whether conscious or not to those involved in making politkal claims-is surely a crucial component in any struggle for political fl'cedom, rhetoric is often treated by historians and political theorists, to Nlly nothing of philosophers, as if it were the mere form in which an _, "'1 aj INTRODUCTION ,{,Ij{.til'(htrt ,,' , independent argument is made. In that case, one could, as it were, packtt!1{jf..,ff!tý age an argument for freedom in the rhetoric of expediency or the social question and then, after freedom has been "attained," shed the packaging like a snake sheds its skin. But things are not so simple. Apart from Riley's account of modern feminism, which suggests that rhetoric does not mere1y reproduce but also constitutes the conditions of political visibility, it is also the case that rhetorical strategies have unintended meanings and effects. Indeed, in feminism, arguments for freedom were not always advanced but rather crippled by their entanglement in social justice arguments and expediency arguments. The point here is not to issue some sort of political complaint or directive (asserting, say, that feminists ought to have made, or ought now to make, arguments for freedom free of social justice claims or expediency claims, or that they should make social justice arguments for freedom free of any trace of rutility). The rise of the social, as described by Arendt, and the entangle,[ ment of women in it, as portrayed by Riley, is an established fact; it is the politically problematic inheritance ofcontemporary feminism. Ifthe task is to try to understand more fully the consequences of that inheritance for feminist democratic politics today, then we need to think carefully and critically about how the social question (and the economy of utility in which it dwells) has framed both our conception of what freedom is (for example, a means to an end: the betterment of society) and what an argument for freedom must look like ifit is to be heard as such (for example, point to something beyond the practice of freedom). Most important, it is to become critically aware of the costs of the social question to freedom itse1f. The history of first- and second-wave feminism shows that to enter into the language game of justifications, be it in the name of social justice or the social question, was more often than not to find onese1f in the losing position, and this is true even if specific goals such as women's suffrage were won. To speak with Arendt on Women's Liberation, "The real question to ask is, what will we lose if we win?,,23 With every attempt to answer their critics in terms of social justice, which was really an argument about expediency, feminists found themselves only falling deeper into the logic of social utility or function that has historically governed every iteration of the "woman question": what is a woman for?24 Feminists have challenged truncated conceptions of what woman is for, usually by questioning the naturalized femininity that supposedly determines her social function. What has been harder to challenge is the logic of social utility itself. This logic keeps women's radicai demand for freer' f I ,~, FEMINISM AND FREEDOM BEGIN WITH F I o dom, for unqualified participation in common affairs, bound to an_econ,omy of llse that deeply restricts their emergence as a political colfectIvity (iiiJIess, ofcourse, we define politics itse1fin terms ofthat same economy). Feminist efforts to substitute the idea of women as a social group (gender) for women as a natural group (sex) may question the substantive social tasks assigned on the basis of sex differences, but without in any way disrupting the logic that tightly binds political life to social utility. The problem with this binding is not only the entanglement of women's citizenship with the social functions of femininity but also the tendency for the value of expediency to trump claims to freedom. If we I .va!:t~_~~I?:~~~Jr~<:~()I!l_j:l~<:?u~ejt_~st.ls~f!!ljll,~()l:ill!LC,ť!E!.~i!!:_~~!~l~11 lems, we may not value freedom when it int~tJ~r.!2§'Yi..th~oc!f!~ utility or il when moreexpeČlient ways of reaching the same social resu[t~--~-a~'l)e- il shown~'FreedOm'distlirbsthe use of politics as a means to an end; itis' \ always "out of order." There is a way to counter the demand that freedom be a means to an end, but it requires that we pose the question of freedom anew and try to find examples of the demand for political freedom that are not easily folded into the social question (or any economy ofutility and means-ends thinking whatsoever). Before we can do that, however, we need to con­ sider another problematic framing of freedom, namely, in terms of the subject question. Freedom as a Subject Question "Since the whole problem of freedom arises for us in the horizon of f!dt/cl Christian tradition on one hand, and ofan originally anti-political phil0- / Iť( I'CI sophic tradition on the other," writes Arendt, "we find it difficult to real-. ize that there may exist a freedom which is not an attribute of the will in,. ( but an accessory of doing and acting."25 At once commonsensical and ". deeply strange, Arendt's account of freedom as political action is highly i t/' critical of the notion of freed()!ILas a phenomenon of.thewiJl, which we, feminist and democratic thi~kers alike;..have inherited from the Western philosophical and political tradition26 Based on Man in the singular, freedom of the will-clearly crucial to but hardly exhausted by the liberal concept offreedom that is domin~nt in most Western democracies- is entangled in a dangerous fantasy of sovereignty, writes Arendt, I according to which "perfect liberty isiincompatible with the existence of society."27 Further, genuine freedom/is defined as the freedom not only I L FEMINISM ANO FREEDOM BEGIN WITH F I 11 10 l INTRODUCTION from the interference of others, or what we calI "negative liberty," but -/; from politics itself. 28 Like the displacement of the political by the social, the identification of freedom with the free will of a sovereign subject is the problematic inheritance of democratic and feminist politicS. 29 Although second- (and to a lesser extent first-) wave feminism criticized the masculinist fantasy of sovereignty that-argued Beauvoir long ago-turns on women's submission, it nonetheless inclined toward a conception of freedom that either sets the individual woman against "all her sex" (that is, the exceptional woman who escapes or denies the social condition of her gender) or requires a woman's full identification with "her sex" (that is, an antipolitical kinship relation in the form of an all-powerful sisterhood that obliterates particularity and with it plurality).3o In both cases, freedom is articulated as sovereignty, be it an "I" against all the others or an " multiplied and extended into an omnipotent "we." The entanglement of feminism in the ideal of sovereignty is symptoatic of a tendency to think about freedom in terms of what I will calI the " ubject question." This question centers prirnarily on the subjecťs very ~ L forrnation and on the external and internal forces that hinder its freedom. The subject question is the larger frame within which a fantasy of sover~ Gignty has been presupposed, but such a fantasy is in no way exhaustive of the frame. What defines the frame is not a certain theory of the subject I (autonomous, dependent, or interdependent) but the fact that !~~ubject I(be it as a philosophical, linguistic, or psychoanalytic category) i~.-!~l J::oi!l!.~ro~~~jliCh_~Y..~tY-l1QJjj:i<;:j~s:~l~_~~SU~fJly-~~~"~p.~f~"!n."."Vhi<;hthiI1.~SJ~~fQ!.it~.P~PlI~"· the space in which, when we act politically, we encounter others who, too, act and take up the effects of our action in ways that we can nev~r predict or control with certainty.47 If it is hard to shift our focus from the question of the subject to that of the world, the space in which things become public, that is because feminist politics has been centered on the "what" (for example, "women" as a coherent identity) and its transformation. This "what" has so captivated our attention that it seems hard to imagine why politics-just as it obviously concerns agency within the subject-centered frame-would not obviously concern the transformation of sociaUy ascribed forms of subjectivity such as gender difference. The obviousness of this political task was as clear for second-wave feminists such as Ti"j Grace Atkinson (who claimed, "those individuals who are today defined ~~;;eIl\l'~s women must eradicate their own definition," in effect "commit sui"I(l'­ cide" in order to give birth to themselves as "individuals") as it is for C.': third-wave feminists such as Wendy Brown (who albeit far more cautiously and with an entirely different notion of subjectivity cali for the transformation of "women" from "wounded subjects" into subjects of freedom).48 In light of such caUs for subject transformation as the very work of political freedom, Arendt's claim that "at the center of politics stands not concern/care for people, but concernlcare for the world" rings as at once FEMIN/SM ANO FREEDOM BEGIN WITH FI'. commonsensical (the world clearly matters) and strange (psychic attach· ments to unfreedom matter toO).49 In Arendťs view, the exclusive con~cern with the self is an expression of the "world-alienation" that characterizes modernity.5o A politics that questions that alienation, sh argues, is not-not in the first place-centered on the subject or the transformation of subjectivity; it is centered on the world and engaged in worldliness, that is, the creation of the space in which things become public. Like her rejection of the social question, Arendťs refusal to count the subject question among the concerns of politics seems perplexing.. Leaving aside the social engineering she criticizes and with which hardly afeminist would disagree, how could apolitics concerned with freedom j not presuppose the transformation of subjectivity? Let's turn the question around: ~hat i~ presupposed bL~QE!i~~ of freedom that centers on the seIf and its transformation? Consider in this regard·Fouca~It;~· welf:knowi;"claim""thät;pra:-~'tke ";;{ freedom is "an exercise of the self on the self by which one attempts to develop and transform oneself, and to attain to a certain mode of being."51 But this idea of freedom as a practice centered on the relation of the self to itself (what Foucault caUs rapport il soi), lest it remain an I-will in the absence of an I-can, surely has its worldly conditions.52 If it is hard to see how such conditions could obtain in Foucaulťs account of freedom, that is because Foucault-like any theorist working from within the frame of the subject question, albeit in its negative space-takes for granted the idea that freedom would begin with changes in subjedivity that then bring about changes in the world, while begging the question of how one changes subjectivity, save in the guise of a highly individualized conception of work on the self.53 The point here is neither to exclude creative work on the self as potentially relevant for political freedom-as Arendt herself might-nor to decide what comes first: changes in the structure of subjectivity or changes in the social structures that constitute subjectivity. It is to think nbout how the subject question and the (ethical) idea of freedom as the self's relation to itself (even in the deeply critical iteration given it by Foucault) might extend, rather than contest, the Western tradition's philosophical conception of freedom and thus the disp!acement of political freedom as a relation to the world and to others.54 Although Foucau1t, like Arendt, clearly refutes the idea of free will and sees that freedom is a practice, not a property of the subject, he does not distin- í'1./i"ŕ'ti(f ~uish acleql1~t.e1Y-_b_ehYf~rLth~_phiIQ~()R.hic?LkindQfft:~"ed~~th~m{iht or (t<ť"~"h bc relevant to solitary individuals and the political kind that is certainly !'c!evant to people"wholiveÍilcommunitie"s: Consequently, hi~otherwiše" ~--. _. 16 I INTRODUCTION valuable assertion that freedom is a practice, something "that must be exercised," risks remaining at the individuallevel without ever founding the new institutions and forms of life that clearly and deeply concerned him.55 political freedom in this sense of world-building cannot simply be rapport asoi (or its extension) but must involve, from the start, relations with a plurality of other people in a public space created by action, that is, by the very practice and experience of freedom itself. Freedom as a World Question "Men are free-as distinguished from their possessing the gift for freedom-as long as they act, neither before nor after; for to be free and to act are the same," declares Arendt.56 Like Foucault, Arendt understands freedom to be an activity or practice, but one that takes place in the sphere of human plurality and that therefore has a distinctive, if mostly lQrZ-Q!!~E--,.J:9~nea~~gy. "We first become awareOIIreeclom or its opposíte in our intercourse with others, not in the intercourse with ourselves," she writes. In agenealogical attempt to recover a political conception of freedom from the occidental tradition, Arendt, like Foucault, returns to the ancients. For her, however, this return does not recover the Greek idea of care of the self (epimeleia heautou) or the notion of freedom as self-rule, as it does for Foucault, but shows that an idea of freedom that begins with the self (rapport ct soi) occludes its origins in freedom "as a worldly tangible reality."s7 This worldly freedom is political: it requires not only an I-will but an I-can; it requires community. Arendt asserts, "Only where the I-will and the I-can coincide does free§!om come to pass."" And furth", "If men wi,h to bc rree, it is prcci"ly , being forgiven, released from the consequences of what we have done, our capacity to act would, as it were, be confined to one single deed from which we could never recover.... Without being bound to the fulfillment of prornises, we would never be able to keep our identities (who we are].... (Keeping them is possible only in] the public realm 18 I INTRODUCTION through the presence of others, who confirm the identity between the one who promises and the one who fulfills.... Both faculties, therefore, depend on plurality, on the presence and acting of others, for no one can forgive himself and no one can feel bound by a prornise made only to himself. (HC, 237) Although the importance of forgiveness in human affairs arose in a religious context, says Arendt, it is by no means irrelevant to secular \ communities (HC, 238-39). Forgiveness sounds strange as a political \"\ concept in part because we think about action in terms of sovereign indi,Alf)\'viduals who use a means to an end, know what they do, and are to be ,aJt~\0/) held accountable for their actions. Arendt does not question accounta- S// bility (though her understanding of it is complex), but she refutes the ,/ assumption of sovereignty. Her concern is that human beings will, in the (~pirit of the tradition, turn away from the public realm for fear that, in \this realm, "they know not what they do," they cannot possibly control Ithe effects of their actions (HC, 239). Likewise, prornising soundsI \~trange as a political concept (though it is surely the basis of any idea of the social contract), for we think about the agreements that constitute political community as guaranteed by law. ~~e..!1d! does not question the role of law in sustaining community, but she refutesthe idea that community originatesin law or can be so guarant~e9. What holds aé~mm~~ity together is, arnong other things in her view, the capacity to make and keep prornises, which is an exercise of freedom. This capacity erects, as she puts it, "isolated islands of certainty in an ocean of uncertainty," namely, the unpredictability that belongs to human action (HC, 244). Those who are mutually bound by promises gain what Arendt calls a "limited sovereignty," not the spurious sovereignty claimed by an individual setting himself apart from all others, but a certain release from the incalculable future that accompanies human action. Finding resources in action to counteract the defining features of action, Arendt does not claim to have discovered perfect safeguards that will protect us from action's boundlessness and unpredictability. Being themselves forms of action, promising and forgiving could hardly play such a role. Her point, rather, is to emphasize that we might live human plurality in ways (for example, through promising and forgiving) that attenuate the problems associated with plurality as the condition of action. That we act into a context characterized by multiple wills and intentions; that others take up our actions in ways we can neither predict nor control, Arendt suggests, is the irreducible condition of human FEMlfIIlSM AND FREEDOM BEGIN WITH fi I ,. action tout court. Rather than seek solace in an impossible fantasy O~ sovereignty, declare a crisis of agency, or turn away from the public real to preserve sovereignty or avoid crisis, we might take leave of the tradi tion and affirm freedom as nonsovereignty. Nonsovereignty is the condition of democratic. politiq;,th~condition of the-t~~nsf~~mati~'~f ~~-í~wm i~to an I-c~n and thus freedo~:Thi~iš a simple point,'b'ut~l~o o~~~e ~re forever in dauger of forgetting (which is why Arendt never tired of repeating it). Political freedom requires oth­ ers and is spatially limited by their presence. No subjective relation of the self to itself, freedom requires a certain kind of relation to others in the space defined by plurality that Arendt caUs the "common world." TjlJ:!_<::Q!llmon world is another..'Y!!y'.QfJ:alking..abQuuhe. n.!lJJlr_~ of democratic-'-afld:-Iargu~',-feminist--:-:-politic.al space. "It is the sp~ce í7&.!{);::kl:l:•• between them that unites them, rather than some quality inside each of -- ---­ them," to cite Margaret Canovan's succinct phrasing of the Arendtian difference between a community based on "what" someone is (that is, on identity) and one based on "who" someone is (that is, on worldbuilding).60 If identities come to have political significance for us, it is because the "what" has been rearticulated as the "who" in the inbetween space of the common world. In this space, plurality is not merely rt numericai matter of the many identities of people who inhabit the earth or a particular geographical territory, nor is it an empiricaI question of the wide variety of groups to which they belong (that is, what people are). A political rather than ontologicai relation based on the ongoing eonstitution of the world as a public space, plurality marks the way in which subjects as members of political communities, as citizens, stand to one another.61 Wbflt. is crucially important for democratic and feminist politics, butmo~tlY_Qccluded. bY-.the_s!Jm~!:.tqll~štion, is that citizéiis bé Asituated in a relation of distance andproximity, ;~íation a~ď~~paration~X "To live together i~the-;~~iJ ~~~s ~š~~;:;:ti~lry-that a world of thingsis between those who have it in common, as a table is located between I'hose who sit around it; the world, like every in-between, relates and sepIll'ates men at the same time," wrítes Arendt (HC, 52). Relates and sepnrates: the common world "gathers us together and yet prevents our fnlling over each other, so to speak" (ibid.). Politics requires and takes place in this in-between space. • In mass societies such as our own, comments Arendt, the world has lost its power to relate and separate us. It is aS if the table had suddenly disappeared from our midst, she wrítes, such that "two persons sitting opposite each other were no longer separated but also would be entirely 20 ! INTRODUCTION unrelated to each other by anything tangible" (HC, 53). Couldn't that also be interpreted as the state of contemporary feminism, in which the price for attending to differences, what separates us, appears to be the absence of anything that relates us? The point is not to assert, in the nostalgic tone attribu'ted-falsely in my view-to Arendt, the loss of something we (feminists) supposedly once had. It is, rather, to see what it would mean to affirm, in a democratic political sense, freedom__~~_.a world-building; pra,ctice based on plurality and nonsovereignty. To _ . _•• _ .........." •• , _____ H ~ ~ a-s~~-~e, as manýfirst~a~ď~~cond-';a~ef~IIliIlistsdid, thät ashared gender identity-is what relates women p~li!!~!1l1y)sfl.ayved not only because, as thTrd:w:ä;e'feminists cläimed,'differences amoIlg.,women matter and the very category of identity itself is suspect. It is fla~edbecauseit does not answer to the question of what possible relevaI1c~identii:ý'can:~~Y~ forfeminist politics absent a space in whichto articulate it as a political relatIOn. Third-wave critiques, too, are mostly sil~nt on how to con'stl'tute the political space in which the transformation of social relations, including gendered forms of subjectivity, is to occur. The common world as the space of freedom is not exhausted by existing institutions or the citizen as the subject of law, but "comes into being whenever men are together in the manner o{speech:a~'~'~s!ist;an,fe:jtL."!11.Y... - .., ""-"''''"'--- -_.,--••.•.._....................... .........." -- .... ' . . f'{'.é't?Nl11 thing. 64 Housework becomes political when two things that are not log- r..· · , ically related, say, the principIe of equality and the sexual division of 'i:~~~?-" labor, are brought into a relationship as the object of a dispute, that is, as the occasion for the speech and action with which people create the common world, the space in which things become public, and create it anew. The same could be said about the practices associated with subject­ constitution that are discussed in both Butler's and Foucault's work. Once again, the point is not to exclude as politically irrelevant those issues that have been framed by the subject question, but to understand what it would mean to frame them anew. Arengt herself did not really consider the possibility of such reframing. Shelcanp~f~~~as rejecting not only thefran:te$Qf bothth~_subject and the social questio~s~b~t'äfs"o the concerns that are assocíated with e~~h-~fth~~~ fr;-rnes:'She seems not only to re)ectthe possibility that slľčh questlons'couflbe relevant to pol­ itics but also to see them as destructive of democratic politics, regardless of how they are articulated. Rather than exdude these concerns, femi?? !lists need to redescribe them in ways that are less likely to lead to the1 displacement of pOliti.caI..fre.e.dom.b.y...th.e.. v.e.. ry..fram.es of the social and the sllbject in which freedomhas been thought.. ._ Ifwe adopt a ~orl~:.~l!~.~~~f political costs of this particular recoil from the abyss?women to their centuries-lollg_sllbjection. And not only neceSS;;l.ry but fustified ÚlO. For it appears once agaInthat freedom must point beyond the demand or practice of freedom itseH, be it to social justice or social I Feminism's "Lost Treasure" \ / and subject questions-miss what is most important: the creation of iÍ.ltility. We find ourselves entangled in justifications that-like the social One risk associated with the tendency to recoil from the abyss of free­\' something new, something that could not have been foretold, that was dom is visible in the stories we teU-or fail to teU-ourselves about the/\ no result of some logical or historical development but rather an "infi­ 66 revolutionary origins of feminism. Although modern feminism did not i \ nite improbability," to borrow Arendt's poetk phrasing. originate in a world-historical event like the American Revolution, it par­What would it mean to think about feminism as an "infinite improbtook of the revolutionary spirit that animates such events, namely whatability"? What would come of rethinking the "we" of feminism as someArendt caUs "the exhilarating awareness of the human capacíty of begin­thing utterly contingent, that is, something that could just as well have ning."69 Akin to the failure of postrevolutionary thought to rememberbeen left undone, something highly fragile that could be driven out of the the simple fact that, writes Arendt, "a revolution gave birth to the Unitedworld? Contingency is a familiarwordin contemporaryieminisr tl1eory,_ 26 I INTRODUCTION States and that the republic was brought about by no historical necessity and no organic development," contemp~!..~L!~!!!i.l!.~.m-,-t09~ee!llS t~ _ha,,~J2§!!;ightQLi!§g,Wl}J2Jig!llÚpjllii:~yQ).ytiQnal:'L.s,picit.and the CQntingency of action. The first two waves of feminism denied the abyssal cli.ru:ac;ter7p~i&al freedom by framing freedom as a social question or "~,subject question or by scripting the claim to freedom as a necessary historical development that flowed directly out of women's liberation from t ifo')p~ression. Feminism of the third wave, for its part, seems to be so thor­ \ / ou~hly caught in the problems associated with these two frames as to 1\ have lost sight of what Arendt poignantly called the "lost treasure" of L~tl}~ American Revolution-political freedom itself. ../ Recent attempts to reclaim feminism as a practice of freedom include narrative accounts of early second-wave feminism that recreatetb.e-exhil: ~.ra~!~g.Y~~l!~~-,9i b~p:pjgg~.~ne~_!~~t animated the individ;;äiilln4. _grOUP!; il!"prx~.cf.·But théše äccoíints;gé-neťitfy-Wrrtten oyi:Iie1C;-ffiícist poIític~l actors themselves, are often characterized by a tone of incredulity and defensiveness, as if third-generation feminists were, when not downright ungrateful, dangerously ignorant of their own political past. Guided by the familiar motto of didactic political historiography-that is, "those who forget the past are destined to repeat it"-many of these accounts treat the past as if it dictates-or ought to dictate-what the future can be.70 ~J~~~4om-centť!red fem.ini~.~ needs not more rallying cries to carry on the cause of past generations-weU, it can use this toobut dis!~.1!K.~~~:tI1Jcl~~oLfeministpractis:~.Lof.PQUriC:;llJr.ee4QI!l: disturbing-if we will only pause and let them disturb us-because t~ resist being incorporated into the social- and subject-centered frames ) iha·t- shape riiósfstóiiešoffemiiiism, frames-lii·whidifreeaomas·action has mostly disappeared. In the following chapters I offer examples of such disturbance in the form of recuperative readings of familiar and unfamiliar, celebrated and castigated, feminist texts that both foreground freedom as a practice and imagine the various practices that freedom can take: freedom as a 112nrule-governe,g theQ!;~t.ic:!'!lpractice (chapter 1); freedom as an inaugural practice of action (chapter 2); freedom as a world-buildingpi.a~tice of promising (chapter 3); and freedom as a critical practic~ofjl1(iging (chapter 4). Although I consider classic claims to political freedom (for example, "Seneca Falls"), the chapters focus on less likely examples: a founding third-wave feminist theory text that is entangled in the ideal of critical reflection it also powerfully contests (Butler's Gender Trouble); a work of literature that relates the world-historical event of a global FEMINISM AND FREEDDM BEGIN WITH F I 27 fcminist revolution organized around the political principIe of freedom (Monique Wittig's Les guérilleres); a collectively authored account of the founding of freedom in an Italian feminist community (the Milan Women's Bookstore Collective's Sexual Difference); and an unfinished project to develop the faculty of judgment on which any capacity to nffirm human freedom depends (Arendťs Lectures on Kanťs Political Philosophy). My choice of Wittig and the Milan Collective as disturbing examples of afeminist practice of freedom may strike some readers as curious. Have their flaws not already been identified (for example, Wittig is a "humanist," the Milan women are "essentialists")? What significanee can they have in the larger scheme of feminist political thought now? It is part of my intention, however, to showhg~gur l:"~c.eiy~d_f[~!!!e~.Q.tth~ !loci::tJ.í:l.n(:L~_~~iect...9.ue~ion,~_j1.E-.Y.Lcfuj:9rt~gJ~ID1Jli$1.rS!adingS.Qi.1hese__ llut4QQ;, blinding us to their concern with freedom and its creation of alternative forms of political association. I reread Wittig and the Milan Collective not only to uncover their rich imagination of political freedom in its various forms, but also to show, in so doing, how it is that we fail to apprehend freedom even when it is instantiated right before our eyes. In the more familiar case of Butler, I examine the critical reception of her early writings on gender, in particular the charge of voluntarism. Although I read (early) Butler as being entangled in a (skeptical) critical enterprise that supports this charge, I also see something else in her project: a contribution to an imaginative, non-rule-governed conception of feminist theory and a nonsovereign practice of freedom. My attempt to read against the grain of feminist interpretation should be understood as an ~x~n:iseinthe.(reflective).judgment that (in chapters 3 and 4) I argue is cr~dali:~ recognizing and affirming freedom and thus to feminism. My choice of authors and texts is guided by a concern to develop the multifaceted idea of political freedom, for each thinker offers a different angle from which to see it. Although it is important to cmphasize the inaugural character of such freedom, the power to begin nnew, we cannot stop there, for freedom so conceived simply turns in cm itself-or at least it risks doing so. An account of political freedoml involves more than spontaneity; it must keep sight of freedom as prac- {, tices of world~bu.ilding (such a~ founding, promising, a~d judging~. The! power of beg10mng a new senes would have no meamng for us 10 the)· absence of our capacity to create and sustain a worldly space in which to. net and judge objeets and events in their freedom. For that reason, I take issue with thinkers who cast freedom strictly in terms of constituent 28 I INTRODUCTION power, setting it at odds with the (non-freedom-centered alternative of) constituted power of law, institutions, and the state. As I show in relartion to the question of constitutionally guaranteed rights for women in \chapter 3, that is a false choice: the point is not to reject but to reclaim \legal artifacts such as rights as part of a practice of freedom in its multi\ple dimensions. \ The tendency to construe false choices infeminism. (for example, con-I "c.c::,---cc· c-c• •....• - 0-·.·.. ...-- - . stituent versus constitutedpower; equality versus difference; recognition versu;'-redIstribuÚon) is largely, in my view, an effect of the frames of the social and subject questions that have guided the development of feminist theory. In chapter 1, I show how the epistemological debates of the 1990s, which centered on the problem of justification, inflected these choices with a sense of crisis, namely, the collapse of "women" as the subject of feminism. The crisis, I argue, was precipitated by a means-ends conception of politics, according to which the ability to make a political \I laim relies on the application of categories as rules to particulars, and by an understanding of feminist theory as the activity of constituting universal rules. Thus the loss of women as a coherent category in theory was ~the loss of a rule that could be so applied. As theory gives the rule to praxis on this view, in the absence of such a category, we have only"differences," no political movement in the name of "women." Or so the story goes. At the heart of these debates was Butler's performative theory of gender. What concerns me in chapter 1 is why Gender Trouble was interpreted in the epistemic terms of a (politically) devastating form of skepticai doubt (for example, "There are no women"), whereas Butler's whole point was to question these same terms. Reading Butler's antirealist account of gender with Wittgenstein's notion of following a rule, I interrogate her paradoxicai entanglement in the skeptical problematic she rejects in favor of a genealogicai approach. Butler's alternative to the epistemic concern with concept application, I argue, emerges with her mostly maligned account of drago Contesting received interpretations, I . see in Butler's discussion of drag{a "figureofthe newly thinkabl~.,J' to borrow Corne1ius Castoriadis's pIir~se: Such figures, given by radicai imagination, are the very condition of critical thought. Whatever doubts we may raise about an "established truth" such as gender always begin with a productive moment of figuration, not (as skepticism would have it) by revealing the ungrounded nature of belief. If we arrive at the insight that a particular belief is ungrounded (as Butler does about a realist idea of gender), that is because we have created a new way of FEMINISM AND FREEDOM 8EGIN WITH F I 29 sceing that enables us to recognize the contingency of a particular social nrrangement. Feminist_.f.ritiq.1!J;!_..lJ;QllcbI.-d~_mus!.~!~§.IHlye thl~J2!9ductive moment~f figuration as its condition. It does not rely-and neednótrefy=oň-~ľ1orm-;;fd~'ub1:-th~t is-i~possible because it is radicaI and totalizing. Having indicated the potential role of imagination for negotiating the impasses associated with the epistemological turn in feminism, I go on in chapter 2 to develop a nonepistemic, action-centered conception of politics and the idea of freedom as the power of beginning. Vividly exhibited in the revolutionary poetics of Monique Wittig, feminism is an inaugural practice: the capacity to bring into existence that which could have been neither predicted nor caused, partly because it exceeds the catt:gory of sex. Like Butler's project, Wittig's work is often taken to be likeptical, as if the category of sex were something we could doubt in its entirety. By contrast with that view, I argue that Wittig fuHy recognizes the limits of doubt for contesting sex as central to our form of life. Her critical approach is not skeptical but productive and creative. Wittig, 1'00, offers a figure of the newly thinkable: les guérilleres, the beginners who break the series of normative heterosexuality and fight for the sole principIe of freedom. But Wittig is less successful in showing the need for and creation of a worldly in-between, that is, the relations that both unite and separate people engaged in a political practice of freedom. For that, I turn to the Milan Women's Bookstore Collective, which conceives freedom as action, but is also concerned with world-building. By contrast with Wittig, the Italians insist that feminist world-building requires the social inscription of~exual differenc:e, not as a form of subjectiv~ty ~ut~s a resolutelyJ?oli~ical p~~(;ticec.:{ď~f.!~~!~la!iol1~.JI:.rp(?_l!S women." These relations involve the articulation of a new social cont:;:;'cr-organized around not female identity (be it natural or social) but w~_wi1lingn(!sst()make ;udgments an4p!p..mis~s._.with. other women_in...3.- pU~,SP!:ls;e... Wholly hased on such practices, female freedom requires no other justification (for example, the betterment of society). Its only raison d'etre is itself. Demonstrating the importance of a worldly in-between, the Milan Collective foregrounds the importance of judgment fqr feminism, but stops short of giving any theoretical account of such a practice. And so, taking up the collective's insight that feminist community ought to be founded not on identity but on a critical practice of making shared judgments, I turn, in chapter 4, to Arendťs idiosyncratic reading of Kanťs third Crítique. In its reflective mode, judgment is the faculty that allows 30 I INTRODUCTION US to apprehend and affirm objects and events in their freedom, to take pleasure in the otherwise frightening arbitrariness of action, and to create feminism as critical community. Emphasizing !Il1~gin~tion, rather than understanding and reason, as cruci~ito-~~cli judgnÍent and as the poHiicáTfačliIiypar-exceHence-;-Arendt helps us understand why the collapse of the category of women need by no means spell the end of feminism, for a freedom-centered feminism never relied on concept application in the first place. Political claims rely on the ability to exercise imagination, to think from the standpoint of others, and in this way to posit universality and thus community. The~ive.!.~