Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' Author(s): Wojciech Sadurski Source: Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 26, No. 2 (Summer, 2006), pp. 377-409 Published by: Oxford University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3877021 Accessed: 04-10-2017 07:13 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3877021?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Oxford Journal of Legal Studies This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 26, No. 2 (2006), pp. 377-409 doi: 10. 1093/ojls/gql008 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' WOJCIECH SADURSKI* Abstract-Is it the case that the law, in order to be fully legitimate, must not o be adopted in a procedurally correct way but must also comply with certain sub stantive values? In the first part of the article I prepare the ground for the discuss of legitimacy of democratic laws by considering the relationship between law legitimacy, its justification and the obligation to obey the law. If legitimacy of law seen as based on the law being justified (as in Raz's 'service conception'), our dut to obey it does not follow automatically: it must be based on some additional ar ments. Raz's conception of legitimate authority does not presuppose, as many c ics claim, any unduly deferential attitude towards authorities. Disconnection of law's legitimacy from the absolute duty to obey it leads to the second part of t article which consists in a critical scrutiny of the claim that the democratically adopted law is legitimate only insofar as it expresses the right moral values. Th claim is shown to be, under one interpretation ('motivational'), nearly meaningl or, under another interpretation ('constitutional'), too strong to survive the pre sure from moral pluralism. While we cannot hope for a design of 'pure procedu democracy' (by analogy to Rawlsian 'pure procedural justice'), democratic proc dures express the values which animate the adoption of a democratic system in t first place. It is often said that a democratic state, in order to be fully legitimate, must not only issue its laws in a procedurally correct way but must also ensure that they comply with certain substantive values. Democracy, it is said, not only requires designing and following the correct procedures but its laws must in addition comply with certain values, such as human dignity, liberty, equal concern for all etc., in order to be fully legitimate. In this article I will subject this understanding-which, for the sake of brevity, I will call the 'democracy-plus' conception-to critical scrutiny. However, my main purpose will not be so much to refute this view, but rather to reflect on what such a call for the alignment of democracy with certain values really means-what plausible interpretations can be given to this demand. More specifically, my main concern will be with the links between 'value-enhanced' democracy (democracy that is not 'merely' * European University Institute in Florence, Department of Law. Email: wojciech.sadurski@IUE.it. I am grateful to Mehreen Afzal, Silvina Alvarez, Adam Czarnota, Zenon Bankowski, Martin Krygier, Neil MacCormick, Euan Macdonald, Gianluigi Palombella, Michel Troper, Lorenzo Zucca and the anonymous referee of the OJLS for their useful comments about an earlier version of this article. I was also helped by discussion of the paper when it was presented at the University of Paris-Nanterre, University of Sevilla, University of New South Wales, Edinburgh University and the University of Parma. ? The Author 2006. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. For permissions, please e-mail: journals.permissions@oxfordjournals.org This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 378 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 procedural but rather claims to have been infused with judgments concerning the legitimacy of democratically the principle of the rule of law can be understood in a pu more substantive way (that is, either that government i whatever they may be, or that it is only subject to those as 'right' or 'just'), so the democratic rule can be unders ner. Can those laws that have procedurally democratic c from our views about the right 'substantive' values still mate? This is a somewhat simplified way of asking the qu cern to me in this article. As the above question immediately suggests, a great deal depends on how we understand the concept of law's 'legitimacy'. In preparing the ground for the discussion of the legitimacy of 'democracy-plus' that will occupy the second part o this article, I will first attempt to elucidate the notion of law's legitimacy by disentangling it from two other contiguous concepts: the justification of law and the obligation of citizens to obey it. I will take, as my starting point, a leading (and perhaps currently the most influential) theory in this area, namely Joseph Raz's so-called 'service conception' of legitimate authority. This choice is informed not merely by the huge critical resonance that this theory has found in recent jurisprudential writings, but, more relevantly from our point of view, by the fact that it has frequently been charged with displaying insufficient respect for th importance of procedurally democratic law-making as a significant factor in judging the legitimacy of laws, and also with underestimating the importance o promoting a critical, reflective attitude in citizens towards the law to which they are subject. The discussion of Raz's conception of legitimacy therefore brings us directly into the heart of the relationship between democratic law-making and the legitimacy of law. Even if, as I will argue, Raz's conception may be unsatisfactory in some regards, this is not due to its alleged disregard for the importance of democracy nor the idea, which it allegedly promotes, that citizens should always defer to authority. The reason that such a suspicion may have arisen in the first place is related to the ambivalence of the very notion of 'legitimacy', and its location vis-a-vis the justification of the law on the one hand and the citizens obligation to obey on the other. I will argue that if legitimacy is understood as relating to the question of a given law's justification, then the objections of Raz' critics are groundless; if, however, legitimacy is viewed as creating or supporting the citizens' duty to obey, then a different, separate argumentative step is required to show that it is legitimate, in addition to being justified. Therefore even if a justification-based understanding of legitimacy does not require that a law have certain procedural, democratic credentials (although, of course, the two are perfectly compatible), this is not necessarily the case when legitimacy i viewed as obligation-inducing. This clears the conceptual ground for a more substantive argument, in the second part of this article, concerning the relationship between legitimacy and This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 379 democracy, and, more specifically, for critical scrutiny of the demand th in order to be legitimate, must embody certain substantive values. Here, look at the warnings against 'democracy without values', and suggest th best way of understanding the 'democracy-plus' precept is to try to imagine w a democracy devoid of substantive values might look like, and what the a tages and disadvantages (if any) of such a system might be. To the exten 'democracy without values' is inconceivable (given that the very choice democratic design is inevitably and strongly value-based), the warning 'democracy without values' is meaningless. However, I will argue that, b this foundational stage, the infusion of democracy with values may be see important and meaningful demand, particularly since, as I will seek to de strate, a resort to the concept of 'pure procedural democracy', by analo Rawlsian 'pure procedural justice', is not readily available to us. We cann sure that, once the democratic procedure has been put in place, the value inform its design will be replicated in the actual functioning of the system. In what way, then, can we plausibly understand the call for 'democracy I will suggest two possible understandings: one 'motivational', the other ' tutional'; and I will show that both exhibit a problematic, troublesome re ship to society's moral pluralism. I will conclude by drawing together t parts of this article, through an analysis of the findings of the second half in light of the discussion of the notion of 'legitimacy' contained in the first. 1. Justification, Legitimacy and the Obligation to Obey A. Legitimate Authority and the 'Service Conception' When is a state justified in issuing authoritative directives to its citizens? And is justified in doing so, does it follow eo ipso that its directives-its laws-a essarily legitimate, leading to the creation of a duty to obey on our part three ideas: the justification of law, its legitimacy, and the obligation of to comply with it, are often conflated with each other in an unhelpful manne this first part of this article, I will attempt to disentangle them in an attemp clear the conceptual field for the later discussion of the legitimacy of dem authorities. A good starting point is Joseph Raz's so-called 'service conception of authority', if only because it is currently so influential, both among its supporters and its detractors. The 'service conception' consists of three theses: the dependence thesis, the normal justification thesis and the pre-emption thesis. Here, I will paraphrase each of these in a stylized manner. According to the first thesis, authoritative directives should only be adopted for reasons which apply to their intended subjects (and not, for example, for reasons relevant to the authorities themselves). The second holds that directives are authoritative when it is the case that desired outcomes (i.e., the outcomes desired by the addressees of the This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 380 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 directives) will be best achieved if the subjects allow them the directives of the authority rather than acting on thos third states that such authoritative directives supersede ment, the reasons for their own adoption. This conception is, at first blush, vulnerable to the objec squared with the idea that citizens should have a critical towards the authorities that govern them; a critical attit democratic society in which it should be generally accept had famously put it, 'however great the aura of majesty o official system may have, its demands must in the end be scrutiny'.' Even though Raz had anticipated objections protested in advance that '[n]o blind obedience to author nevertheless the charge has been laid. Ronald Dworkin, f rather caustically that '[t]his account of the nature and point on a certain attitude toward authority',3 namely, 'a degre legal authority that almost no one shows in modern dem looking more closely at Dworkin's argument: We do not treat even those laws we regard as perfectly valid and and replacing the background reasons the framers of that law adopting it. We rather regard those laws as creating rights an trump those other reasons. The reasons remain, and we som them to decide whether, in particular circumstances, they are so ful or important that the law's trump should not prevail.5 Dworkin then goes on to elaborate this point by giving th Abraham Lincoln who, during the Civil War, suspended t pus even though the US Constitution denies such a power ing on his own, instead assigning it to Congress. Dworkin's criticism, however, misses the point, and his ally seems to confirm rather than undermine Raz's conce gesting, as far as I understand him properly, that citizen the authority's directives instead of following their own rather, he is saying that if they do so, then the authority is, This is a conceptual analysis of the notion of legitimate au normative view about the scope of subjection of citizens t language that Dworkin uses to describe the status of the subjects after the law has entered into the scene actually conf duties created by the law 'trump' the original reasons-w 'H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (1961) at 206. 2 Joseph Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain (1994) at 215 3 Ronald Dworkin 'Thirty Years On (Book Review of The Practice of Principle b Law Review 1655 at 1671 (2002). 4 Ibid at 1672. 5 Ibid. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 381 Raz describes by using the language of 'pre-emption'. 'The reasons rema Dworkin observes, but this does not mark any difference between the (R pre-emption thesis and Dworkin's own account, because the reasons 'rem only in the sense that they inform us whether, under the circumstanc should comply with the law's directives, or perhaps contemplate some e legal, even illegal, course of action. This residual role of the original reason law has entered the stage is perfectly compatible with-indeed, supports pre-emption thesis, because on his account the limits to the pre-emption the same time the limits of law's legitimacy. When the law's 'subjects d guide their actions by its instructions instead of by the reasons on which they supposed to depend'6 then the law, at this point, is no longer a legitimate ity for them because it does not fulfil the role of mediating between peop the practical reasons upon which they act-a 'mediation' central to Raz's account.7 Dworkin's example of Lincoln and his suspension of habeas corpus seems to confirm this: 'Most of us treat the Constitution as both legitimate and authoritative. But many commentators nevertheless think both that Abraham Lincoln was morally right to suspend habeas corpus during the Civil War and that he acted illegally'.8 Expressed in Raz's terms, what Lincoln did was to revert to the original reasons for action rather than to act on the Constitution's authority: the perceived emergency inclined him into an illegal but politically and morally preferable solution. Far from undermining Raz's pre-emption thesis, Dworkin's argument actually confirms Raz's account in his own parlance: legal rights normally 'trump' our various extra-legal considerations (e.g. of utility), but extra-legal considerations may 'trump' the law's authority when compliance with law's directives is morally or politically indefensible. This becomes even clearer when Dworkin adds: Lincoln did not deny the Constitution's authority in making his decision; he sim weighed that authority against competing reasons of the kind the Framers had taken into account which retained their vitality. Lincoln found that the latter under the circumstances, strong enough to outweigh the former.9 It is puzzling why Dworkin sees this account of Lincoln's unconstitutiona morally and politically justified action as contrary to Raz's account of what stitutes legitimate authority. The point of Dworkin's account is as follows: Framers of the US Constitution had contemplated various reasons that the ident and/or Congress might have for suspending the writ, and in the end decided that the reasons for the President to act alone were not compelli 6 Raz, above n 2 at 215. 7 Ibid at 214: '[The dependence and the normal justification theses] regard authorities as mediating be people and the right reasons which apply to them, so that the authority judges and pronounces what they o do according to right reason' [emphasis in original]. 8 Dworkin, above n 3 at 1672. 9 Ibid at 1672. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 382 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 enough to grant him this constitutional power. Those re carded by the Framers) 'retained their vitality' neverthele legal realm, so to speak), and Lincoln acted on them, in Constitution provided; hence, he acted illegally, but, in th 'many commentators' with whom he aligns himself, mora perfectly compatible with Raz's account: in Raz's terminol issue, Lincoln decided that it was better to revert to his o (which, we may imagine, had something to do with the m avoiding great national disaster in a situation of emerge dated his unilateral action to suspend the writ) rather tha directives contained in the Constitution as the best way of original reasons. So in this particular case, he denied the stitution, which is just another way of saying, as Dworkin Lincoln acted 'illegally' and at the same time in a 'morally There is one way in which the above defence of Raz's con lenged, and its consistency with Dworkin's account of the tioned. It may be argued that the property of legitimacy a across the board and not to its specific directives, so that a su one or another specific directive of an authority (or, in Raz's her own reasons for action rather than allow the authorit empt them) and still recognize the legitimacy of the authorit interpretation seems to be offered by Dworkin when he state 'Lincoln did not deny the Constitution's authority in making that 'he acted illegally'. This, however, seems to be a peda that Lincoln 'acted illegally' on this particular issue means issue, he denied the legitimacy of the Constitution as applyin nition of legitimacy may be a matter of degree: Raz actually system's legitimate authority 'may not be as extensive as i course, adopt by definitional fiat a convention whereby legit the authority as a whole rather than to its particular directiv need another language to describe the situation in which a general authority of a given entity, but refuses to recognize properly incorporating the right reasons relevant to himself. ing that such a specific directive held to be 'illegitimate' by t ing is gained by attributing the notion of legitimacy only to and denying it to specific authoritative directives. B. Authority and Identification of Valid Law Raz's pre-emption thesis seems therefore to be a useful enoug means for subjects to treat an authority as legitimate. Wh o10 Raz, above n 2 at 215. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 383 however, is the account of the law as necessarily and always identifiable w regard to the original reasons that the law-makers have amalgamated, s speak, into the legal directives. It is one thing for Raz to insist on the con truth about 'legitimate' authorities pre-empting the citizens' appeal to no reasons insofar as they recognize the legitimacy of a given directive; it is anot thing altogether to claim that the law must be fully identifiable by its s without ascertainment of the original reasons for action that it is now m displace. The latter claim is not a necessary condition of the intelligibility former. We can say that, insofar as we recognize the law's legitimacy, we disrega competing, non-legal reasons for action (in the sense that if those non-leg siderations outweigh the legal directives, then this is just another way of that the law's legitimacy has reached its limits), and also that in order to ascer the correct meaning of the legal directives, we must appeal, at times, to t reasons that the law seeks to translate into the language of legal rules. The statement may upset the architectural elegance of Raz's construction in th that the original reasons for action may appear twice in the process of th pliance with law: first, at the stage of the translation of citizens' reasons into rules by legal authorities; and secondly, at the stage of ascertaining the m of those legal rules by those to whom they are addressed. This, however, as problematic as it may at first seem: it is not contradictory to claim, at the time, that (1) to treat the law as a legitimate authority means to surrend appeal to the original (non-legal) reasons in deciding about one's action, basis that the law effectively translates those reasons into its directives, a (2) in order to identify the meaning of the legal directives we need, at ti refer back to those original (non-legal) reasons. Simultaneous acceptance these two propositions, untidy though it may seem, has the advantage of the concept of law from patently counter-intuitive conclusions, accord which a number of legal standards would have to be denied the quality precisely because in order to ascertain their meaning, the subjects need to to the reasons that triggered the elevation of these standards to legal status in first place. This, indeed, is the meaning of 'standards' in those contexts when, in theory, they are contrasted to 'rules' (not to be confused with Dworkin's ples/rules distinction)." When, for instance, the law denies enforceabili those contracts that 'unreasonably' restrain trade, or prohibits 'establishm a religion, etc., then it calls upon its subjects to replicate in their minds t sons for action that it now purports to 'pre-empt'. In order to fix the meanin those standards (and therefore, of the authoritative directives of law) its s 1 See, in particular, Duncan Kennedy, 'Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication', 89 Harvard Review 1685 (1976); Kathleen Sullivan 'The Supreme Court, 1991 Term-Foreword: The Justices of Ru Standards', 106 Harvard Law Review 22 (1992); Jeremy Waldron, 'Legal and Political Philosophy' in Jule and Scott Shapiro (eds), The Oxford Handbook on furisprudence and Philosophy of Law (2002), 352-81 at 35 This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 384 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 must go back to the original reasons for enacting them in sure, it is not a simple replication of the process of translatio sons into directives, because the very fact of already ha legal directives in force introduces some important const ings that can be given to them (and this is the point of Dwor structive interpretation in law).12 An enforcer of a legal the same freedom of interpretation as the legislators and argued for the introduction of the rule in the first place. If hibits, for example, the establishment of a religion, then which actions, under the interpretative conventions of a g be viewed as the unconstitutional establishment of relig those constraints, in order to ascertain exactly what is and instance, whether state financial aid to religious schools ment' or not), an enforcer of this legal directive will ha underlying purposes, principles and/or policies that it is s We know that the law mediates between the background authoritative decisions, and at times to identify the mean directives we need to look back to the original reasons tha Indeed, law-makers may justifiably intend, in some circums do just this, for instance in order to introduce some necessar law at the stage of its application (because flexibility at th may often be politically unfeasible), or to avoid incidence tice caused by the scrupulous application of a by-and-larg reduce the levels of over- and under-inclusiveness that ne the background policies and principles are 'translated' in rules, or for a whole host of other reasons.'3 We (i.e. the of those directives) will then need to engage in the ascertainm of those background principles and policies, and also in a r ing of the values at stake, thus largely replicating the m within the constraints of valid interpretative conventions) th adoption of the directive. We may express this proposit Dworkin's 'constructive interpretation', or in the langua called 'inclusive positivism' who claim that law, at times, standards into the meaning of its authoritative rules. Eith essential to the very notion of authority is the idea that the tive directives should be identifiable without recourse to the the directives supposedly pre-empt cannot be squared wit ence of 'standards' (as opposed to 'rules') in legal directives. Nor can it be squared with the fact that the distinction between standards and rules is a more a matter of degree than of a sharp divide: many directives, which at first blush look 12 Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (1986) at 62-8. 13 Including to promote civic deliberation in the process of adjudication, see Sullivan, above n 11 at 67-9. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 385 like straight rules, may be 'corrupted by exceptions''"4 to the point at which t more closely resemble standards. C. Legitimate Authority and Democracy Raz's conception of legitimate authority is not a normative thesis about legitimacy should be generated but rather a conceptual analysis of what it for authority to be legitimate. The source of misunderstanding about Ra ception may be that Raz himself is not quite clear about this distinction b the possible aspirations of his project. Recently, one of his critics, Scott Hersh claimed that the 'normal justification thesis' neglects the importance of procedural mechanisms of democracy: If a government's electoral system favors some interests in society, or appears cor financed, or causes portions of the population to be marginalized and voiceless, quick to judge it illegitimate, or at least less legitimate than it might be other Where these deficiencies are present, it counts for little that a government may p substantively good decisions, decisions that the normal justification thesis [o would hold authoritative. ... This shows us one way in which the normal justif thesis is incomplete as a theory of legitimacy for political authorities: Governmen fulfill it may fail to be legitimate on procedural grounds." The source of the confusion is that, in offering his conception, Raz is ap ently less interested in the problem of legitimacy than in that of authori avowed aim is to tell us what it means for one person or entity to have a ity over another. But to construct the concept of authority, Raz choose take as a point of departure the notion of legitimate authority. It is only we learn what legitimate authority means that we can discover what a l than-legitimate authority is, by identifying what features it lacks in com with a legitimate one. And so we learn from Raz that 'the law either cl that it possesses legitimate authority, or is held to possess it or both', an even if the law fails to posses legitimate authority, it is a conceptual trut it must at least 'claim' to do so.16 (As Dworkin has observed, this is in m respects a bizarre proposition, but we may leave this matter to one side here)." So it is not the case that, according to Raz, we first develop a concept of authority and then add to it the conditions of its legitimacy; rather, the converse seems to be the case, as the very concept of authority is not intelligible without a prior notion of legitimate authority. (It is rather as if we defined 'postage stamps' by defining 'valid postage stamps' first, and only then explained that there are also stamps which lack some conditions of validitybut the very idea of a 'postage stamp' is unintelligible without knowing first 14 Ibid at 61. 15 Scott Hershovitz, 'Legitimacy, Democracy, and Razian Authority', 9 Legal Theory 201 at 216 (2003). 16 Raz, above n 2 at 215 17 Dworkin, above n 3 at 1666-7. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 386 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 what a valid stamp means).'" This is confirmed when Raz in general can be divided into legitimate and de facto auth claims to be legitimate or is believed to be so'.19 Either whether legitimate or not, derives conceptually from the pro Legitimacy, or the lack thereof, is in the eyes of the critica authority either commands 'legitimacy' by virtue of the belie at the very least claims to be legitimate, even if it fails t among its subjects. Under Raz's definitional proposal, an 'a claims legitimacy nor is believed to be legitimate is a contrad seems acceptable: indeed, we have a different vocabulary that does not even try to create pretensions of legitimac force, etc. The use of the language of 'authority' carries a ific acknowledgement of a (real or at least claimed) conn exercise of the authority and certain facts about the subj (namely, about the reasons for action that they have indep ence of the authority itself). 'An authority' that did not e such a connection, and yet were successful in controllin subjects, would not be even an 'illegitimate' authority; it would not be an 'authority' at all, representing nothing but naked power. Whether the 'authority' is legitimate or not is a matter of its degree of success (in the eyes of a critical observer) in establishing a close connection between its directives and the background reasons that would otherwise guide the actions of the laws addresseesin Raz's terminology, 'reasons which apply to the subjects of those directives'. Viewed in this way, Raz's theory is immune to the criticism that it neglects the importance of procedural devices of democracy. His project is to suggest a concept of authority that necessarily relies upon a prior concept of legitimacy, rather than to propose a normative political theory about what are the necessary and sufficient conditions of legitimacy. But the concept of authority he outlines lends itself well to the democratic interpretation suggested by Hershovitz: it is only a matter of interpreting the meaning of 'the reasons which apply to the subjects' of authoritative directives. We may recall that Raz claimed in his 'dependence thesis' that the very concept of (legitimate) authority requires that directives be based 'on reasons which apply to the subjects of those directives'; the whole point of the 'service conception' is to place the (legitimate) authorities in the position of mediating between the subjects and 'the right reasons which apply to 18 Another analogy may be drawn from an argument in the House of Lords' decision Anisminic Ltd and Foreign Compensation Commission and Another [1969] 2 AC 147 at 199 per Lord Pearce, in which one of the questions concerned the meaning of the word 'determination' as in the 'determination by the Foreign Compensation Commission' in the text of the Act of 1950 establishing the Commission; the judgment established that only 'a real determination, not a purported determination' was to be construed as a 'determination'. Otherwise an absurd situation would be reached, according to Lord Pearce, in which the court deliberating on the Commission's decision would not be able to inquire as to 'whether a purported determination was a forged or inaccurate order which did not represent that which the commission had really decided'. To paraphrase, for the purposes of our argument, the notion of 'purported' or 'forged' or 'invalid' determination is derivative of the notion of a valid, or proper, determination. 19 Raz, above n 2 at 211. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 387 them'.20 But what reasons can 'apply to the subjects' other than those th actually have? To be sure, one can suggest that paternalistic non-democ authorities (perhaps in the idealized version offered by Rawls when he de decent and well-ordered, though illiberal, societies)21 can better identify t sons that 'apply to the subjects' than can the subjects themselves. This, ho is a matter of normative political philosophy; manifestly not what Raz eng when describing his 'service conception'. So it is perfectly compatible wit theory to claim that the only way for the authorities to ascertain 'the reasons apply to the subjects' of authoritative directives is by asking those subjects th selves, through democratic elections, representative bodies, referenda, etc bining such a (very plausible) normative political philosophy with Raz's 's conception' brings about precisely what Hershovitz claims (although he p his claim as a criticism of Raz's thesis), namely, that the only authority t be legitimate under the service conception is one that is procedurally dem The fact that Raz's conception can be reconciled also with a non-demo paternalistic theory (according to which the authorities are legitimate i properly discern the reasons relevant to their subjects without asking the sub themselves what they take those reasons to be) is not an argument agai service conception, because Raz might simply retort that, as a matter of n tive political philosophy, he considers the paternalistic conception deeply implausible. Therefore, while Raz's understanding of legitimate authority is broad enough to accommodate various democratic and non-democratic political theories alike, the use of this concept does not reveal indifference towards democratic procedures. This is quite simply a separate debate (about how to go about identifying the reasons relevant to the subjects of authority), and Raz is free to claim that democracy offers the only plausible solution. D. Justification and Obligation At the start of this part of the article, I stated that I would deal here with justification, legitimacy and the obligation to obey the law, but thus far I have focused exclusively on legitimacy; it is now time to consider the other two categories. Let us begin with the relationship between the legitimacy of law and the obligation to obey it. There is an understandable temptation, at a commonsense level, to draw a tight conceptual connection between the two: while there is no reason to obey a law which is illegitimate or the legitimacy of which is in doubt, what is the point (the argument may go) of ascertaining the legitimacy of a given law other than to identify our obligation to obey it? As in Shakespeare's 'Henry IV', when Glendower boasts, 'I can call spirits from the vasty deep', and Hotspur retorts: 'Why, so can I, or so can any man;/But will they come when you call for them?',22 20 Ibid at 214. 21 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (1999), esp at 59-88. 22 William Shakespeare, Henry IV, Part I, Act 3, Scene 1 This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 388 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 a finding that a law is legitimate may appear pointless unless nected to the validation of the duty to obey it. Indeed, that we may have at times an obligation to obey laws that legitimate, and so, a fortiori, have an unquestionable obliga imate law. Consider John Finnis's proposition that 'if an tion is, in fact, homogeneous with other laws in its formal so by courts and officials, and in its common acceptance, the always) be morally required to conform to that stipulatio sary to avoid weakening 'the law', the legal system (of rules, positions) as a whole'.23 This is because, in the case of particular unjust law that is an aberration in an otherwise rea we should be concerned about not undermining the effe system as a whole in pursuing the common good. Hence it case of a law that we consider to be legitimate (by our o they may be) our moral obligation to comply must be all t The connection, however, is not as close as it would seem at significant that for a number of legal theorists the obligator not necessarily follow from their legitimacy. Kent Greenawal a number of different correlates of the idea of a legitimate p the proposition that the governed should obey the directives ity is only one among a number of others possible, such as ical authority are justified in issuing certain kinds of di govern, or that they are justified in using force to induce co governed should not interfere with such uses of force, et Ladenson has suggested that 'The right to rule is ... a jus [which] by itself implies nothing about either the subject the state or of compliance with the law'.25 Indeed, the vi legitimate authority merely connotes that the authority is ju tives to the subjects, but not that the subjects have a corresp ply with these directives, seems to be quite widespread in cur To see clearly why this disconnection of legitimacy and o eminently persuasive, it suffices to consider again Raz's u mate authority (the 'service conception'). According to t have seen, those subject to the authority are more likely tives founded upon reasons relevant to them. This means sons that people espouse identify important aspects of the understood, and that they are more likely to attain this wellwith the authoritative directives rather than attempting to a (or, in Raz's terminology, through acting on those reaso implication of this conception is that it is rational, or wis 23 John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (1980) at 361-2. 24 R. Kent Greenawalt, Conflicts of Law and Morality (1987) at 50-1. 25 Robert Ladenson, 'In Defense of a Hobbesian Conception of Law' in J. Raz (ed This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 389 subjects of an authority to follow authoritative directives (which already, und legitimate authority, correctly incorporate the original reasons) rather than t find their own way of attaining those aspects of their well-being. No-one ever, has a duty to be rational, or wise, or prudent.26 To establish such a requires some additional normative argument. If I choose to ignore the tives issued by legitimate authorities (directives that, by definition, better re the reasons which apply to me than any unilateral action I could take), make my life more difficult, and fail to attain most efficiently the goals iden by my original reasons-but I have not breached any obligation. I would breached an obligation if, for instance, by disregarding the authoritative tives and acting on my own reasons directly, I failed to discharge duties o ness to my fellow-citizens (who do follow the authoritative directives in that pre-empts their own, original reasons for action), or if I undermine law's effort to provide the optimal coordination of individual actions in p of public goods, or if I reneged on an implied promise to obey the law, others might have legitimately read into my conduct and relied on in t actions, and so on. However, each of these grounds for alleging a breach obligation requires an additional theory about the foundations of my oblig that, for example, the law parallels the schemes of cooperation that gen reciprocal duties of fairness; or that law is generally efficient in coord individual actions to deflect collective-action problems and that when it is fied as such, we all have a duty to contribute to such an efficient outco that our continued presence in the society can be viewed as analogous to implicit promise to be bound by a legitimate law, etc. Each of these theori or may not be persuasive-and, as we know, entire libraries can be filled w erature arising from the disputes and disagreements over these, and other posed grounds for a political obligation. One thing, however, is clear: the additional theories that are necessary to provide a moral basis for a duty t ply with a legitimate law, and that a concept of legitimate authority, such as proposed by Raz, evidently does not ground, per se, such a duty. However, the matter is more complicated than that, and Raz's is not th theory of legitimate authority around. It is worth looking at those theorists w in contrast to Greenawalt,27 Ladenson and others, draw a strict connec between legitimacy and the duty to obey. Perhaps the most interesting versio 26 This is consistent with what Raz had claimed well before he has formulated his 'service conception of ity', namely that there is no general moral obligation to obey the law; more specifically, he showed that s obligation does not follow from our undeniable duty to support and uphold good institutions (and so, in th language, the institutions that properly translate our original reasons into authoritative directives). The dut port good institutions, Raz says, gives birth to an obligation to obey only those laws that guarantee the fun of a democratic government, while 'It provides reasons to obey other laws only to the extent that by doin sets a good example or that by failing so to act one sets a bad example: that is, only to the extent that obe these other laws strengthens or prevents weakening the laws on which the democratic character of the gov is founded', Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law (1979) at 241. 27 To be sure, one of Greenawalt's seven possible 'correlates' of state's legitimacy is a duty to obey it by zens. I have here, and in my next reference to Greenawalt, taken into account only those 'correlates' wher implication is proposed. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 390 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 such a conception was recently proposed by A. John Sim (what he calls) a 'Lockean account' (which is also his, Sim of state legitimacy in the following way: A state's (or government's) legitimacy is the complex moral rig exclusive imposer of binding duties on its subjects, to have it these duties, and to use coercion to enforce the duties. Accordi the logical correlate of various obligations, including subjects' state's 'legitimacy right' is in part a right held specifically again any state-imposed duties, arising from morally significant re consensual relations-between state and subject.28 Simmons goes on to elaborate on the last point in this quo nature of the 'special moral relationship with any particul the state a moral legitimacy, which in turn creates a duty of the subjects. His discussion, inspired by Locke, is comp pose to summarize it here, but the main point (for our Locke, as for Simmons, the moral justification of a state i tion of its legitimacy quite another. Moral justification is a m and applauding, the general quality of a state, such as its various coordination problems, to institutionalize and enfo violence, etc. To justify states we need to show that they course not all states are beneficial; hence, not all states ar justified, this fact may, at best, ground our duty not to und even positively to support it-but not necessarily to obey it. Obedience is another matter: it requires some special relationship between the state and a particular subject, because '[t]he fact that a state or a business has virtues that can be appealed to in order to justify its existence cannot by itself argue for its having special rights over particular individuals'.30 Those 'special rights' constitute the state's legitimacy-and they have to be defended on some other grounds (which Simmons characterizes as 'morally significant relationship' between the state and a particular individual) than merely the net benefits of having a state (or that state) that justify its existence. Thus far I have been dealing with legitimacy without making any distinction between the legitimacy of particular rules and the legitimacy of a system of legal rules as a whole. Indeed, as I suggested earlier, legitimacy may be a matter of degree, and the legitimacy of a system may be seen as emerging from the recognition of the legitimacy of a great many specific legal directives that it contains. From the citizens' point of view, however, which is that of the legal obligation to obey, disobedience can normally be expressed only with regard to specific legal rules, not to the system as a whole. In such circumstances, as John Finnis noted, 28 A. John Simmons, 'Justification and Legitimacy' (1999) 109 Ethics 739 at 746. 29 Ibid at 748. 30 Ibid at 752. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 391 'your allegiance to the whole system ('the law') is put on the line: either obey the particular law, or you reveal yourself... as lacking or defective i giance to the whole, as well as to the particular'.31 It would appear, therefore, there is an important asymmetry between the problems of the legitimacy and obligatory nature of the law: the former crystallizes only at the level of parti law, while the latter does so at both the particular and systemic level. Th tinction between the particular and the systemic needs not concern us, ho because the asymmetry just noted does not affect the relationship between imacy and obligation in a way damaging to the argument here. After all, if le macy is based, as in Simmons' work, on special grounds that link the stat the individuals, then these grounds may equally concern specific laws or t tem as a whole. And if legitimacy is based upon 'dependent reasons' bein rectly encapsulated in legal directives, as in Raz's understanding, then legi is even more readily identifiable at the level of particular rules. Similar repeated disobedience to a great number of particular laws amounts to a g habit of disobedience, which may or may not be based on a citizen's ref grant legitimacy to the legal system as a whole. However, there is no reaso we cannot say that someone may accord general legitimacy to the system whole, while at the same time refusing to obey a particular law on the bas she finds it illegitimate.32 Simmons' conception nicely demonstrates a general proposition that I w make at this point, in bringing together the three concepts that I referre the start of this section: justification, legitimacy and the obligation to obe general proposition is this: either justification and legitimacy are taken to be s stantively the same thing (or, to be more precise, rely on substantively th arguments) and then the obligation to obey requires separate moral argum than those used to support the other two (as in Raz, Greenawalt and Lade or justification and legitimacy are two different things (each requiring dif sorts of moral arguments) but then the obligation to obey follows nece from the validation of a state as legitimate (as in Simmons). To simplify, the trichotomy of justification/legitimacy/obligation to obey, the notion of l macy is strategically central: either we align it with justification (and hav sonably weak notion of legitimacy, equivalent to the state being justifie issuing directives) or with an obligation to obey (and then we have a stron cept of legitimacy, equivalent to the duty of compliance). What we cannot the alignment of all three concepts with each other because we then lose s 31 Finnis, above n. 23 at 317, emphases in the original. 32 Consider Dworkin's proposition: 'A state is legitimate if its constitutional structure and practices are its citizens have a general obligation to obey political decisions that purport to impose duties on them. An for legitimacy need only provide reasons for that general situation. It need not show that a government, leg that sense, therefore has moral authority to do anything it wants to its citizens, or that they are obligate every decision it makes', Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (1986) at 181, emphasis added. The italicized w indicate the availability of yet another 'sense' of legitimacy, namely pertaining to specific legitimacy of p laws. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 392 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 the crucial fact that we do not have a duty to obey a stat that it is properly doing what it is supposed to do. Wheth fact that the state is performing well its proper functions in service conception of legitimate authority (and say that incorporating the dependent reasons into its authoritative its subjects rational reasons to suppress their own indepen and to act on the state directives directly), or in the langu justification of a state, is ultimately unimportant, and may b definitional fiat. What is important is the awareness that ing: 'justification-legitimacy-duty to obey' we always ha mentative steps, not just one; and that we should avoid moving directly from a moral justification of a state to the p citizens. 2. 'Democracy-Plus' A. 'Democracy Without Values' A few years ago, speaking before the Polish Parliament ('Sejm') Pope John Paul I urged his audience-the parliamentarians of a newly democratized State-not to ignore the importance of the right moral values: 'Whilst the autonomy proper t the life of a political community must be respected, it should also be borne in mind that a political community cannot be seen as independent of ethical princi ples'.33 He then went on to quote his own Encyclical, Veritatis Splendor, of 1993 'As history demonstrates, a democracy without values easily turns into open or thinly disguised totalitarianism'.34 As we can see, the late Pontiff phrased the questions of the conditions of democratic legitimacy in a remarkably similar way to that in which I framed the issue at the start of this article: namely, that democracy must be enhanced with values-'democracy-plus', in my proposed vocabulary-in order to provide a strong basis for the legitimacy of democratically established legal directives. 'A political [democratic] community cannot be seen as independent of ethical principles'; 'a democracy without values easily turns into open or thinly disguised totalitarianism'. What is the meaning of these warnings? The only way w can make sense of them is, I believe, by imagining what the negatives would be like: what a democratic community 'independent of ethical principles' or a 'democracy without values' might look like. Just as we can sometimes articulat intelligibly the shape of a positive precept (say, 'wealth with wisdom') only by realizing the shape, and the consequences, of its negative counterpart ('wealth without wisdom'), so we can give a proper meaning to the call for infusing 33 John Paul II, 'Address to the Polish Parliament', 11 June 1999, available at http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/ john_paulii/travels/documents/hfjp-ii_spe_ 1061999_warsaw-parliament_en.html part 5, my emphasis. 34 Ibid, part 5, quoting Pope John Paul II, Veritatis Splendor, 6 August, 1993, my emphasis. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 393 democracy with values only by thinking about what 'democracy without val would be like, and what would be wrong with it. However, such a thought experiment is less easy than it may at first appe For one thing, democracy as a system is based on particular, strong (and, b implication, controversial) moral values. The very choice of a democratic sy tem, and a commitment to the maintenance and defence of democracy aga the alternative institutional systems, is not in itself value-neutral. Perhaps most obvious moral value that is necessarily presupposed by a democratic s tem is that of equal moral agency of every human being in terms of influenc decisions about public arrangements. What other reasons would we have adopt a majority-rule based institutional design (which is, subject to all poss caveats and reservations, the irreducible hard core of any democracy)35 if we not adopted, as an overarching political value, some precept about the e moral agency (or dignity) of all? After all, under many plausible and empiric testable conceptions, the conferral of an equal vote upon every adult citizen matters of common concern, is deeply irrational and arbitrary. People var widely in terms of their intelligence, knowledge, experience, moral integrit honesty, contributions to public welfare, courage, and so on. Each of these pr erties (and many others) could be shown to be relevant to the exercise of a r to affect public decisions; hence, each could constitute a ground of reducing enhancing one's 'vote' on public issues, for instance, in parliamentary electio If, intuitively, we find such a proposed radical departure from a 'one pers one vote' principle objectionable (as, I take it, we usually do) then it must b because there are some powerful moral values that would be offended by suc departure. Of course, we may be hesitant to embark upon such a path also non-moral reasons: we might think, for instance, that it will be increasing costly to test and assign the vote based on any of such proposed criteria; or it might increase the potential for corruption and moral hazard; or we may rejec it because any agreement to such a proposed re-assignment of votes would i have to be subject to a justifiable re-weighing of votes, which runs us into an inf nite regress, etc. But while each of these objections is serious, taken toget they would not be weighty enough if we sincerely thought that the principl one person-one vote was fundamentally morally flawed; furthermore, we w be much more determined than we currently are about finding a more mor justified system, and only then start worrying about the practical difficultie putting the alternative into practice. 35 There is of course a major and deliberate simplification in this account: there is no single, canonical conce tion of democracy, and the implications for the equality of voters are different if we opt for a purely majorita procedural theory of democracy, or a constitutional conception with strong substantive rights limiting the sc the majority decision, or a deliberative democratic conception that attempts to overcome the procedural-constitu distinction and identifies the main criterion of democracy in deliberation among the citizens with the aim of justifyi their collective decisions to one another. For this trichotomy of procedural, constitutional and deliberative dem cracy, see Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (1996) at 26-51. At this stage of argument, however, all that matters is that, regardless of where, how, and to what extent the majority rule ope it inevitably relies on some prior egalitarian presuppositions. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 394 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 So it is like ascertaining the existence of a planet not by but rather by drawing inferences from the puzzling beha planets: the fact that we intuitively reject, on moral gro apportioning the vote on the grounds of, for example, in assumption of a powerful value (or a set of values) that tr prima facie plausible, grounds for differential assignmen What might this other, powerful value be? Not surprisingly, disagree among themselves about its specific articulation approaches towards it are a direct reflection of different cracy that we support. Any attempt to identify a single v accepted by all those who espouse democracy is ultimately to use Ronald Dworkin's characterization applied to polit both an 'interpretive' and an 'integrated' ideal.36 It is, fir sense that people not only disagree about the value of dem gree about what democracy really is, and no 'Archimedea able in order to establish, in a descriptive manner, the m before we get on with the debates about its worth. And, grated' (rather than a 'detached') ideal in the sense that of democracy are only revealed through their place in a l values, which mutually reinforce and confer worth upon e One might think that this characterization of democracy and integrated (in the Dworkinian sense) detracts from th is a 'foundational' value behind democracy, such as that o It does not, however; indeed, it only strengthens the view th based in a sense that renders the concept of 'democracy w meaningless. For we may disagree over what specific acco ues that justify democracy in the first place: some will di logical grounds for such values,37 while others will insis upon equal rationality free from any transcendental pre different articulations of democracy-justifying values will yi ent conceptions of democracy itself, and there is nothing ing about this. What matters is that there must be some adopted and defended, and whose general contours are by in order to counter and outweigh the prima facie rational aristocratic, or technocratic models of collective decision and-large egalitarian values must be powerful enough to d from the rationality of apportioning the power of the vote a competences as measured by a person's intelligence, educ 36 See Ronald Dworkin, 'Hart's Postcript and the Character of Political Philos and 14-16. 37 See, e.g. Jeremy Waldron, God, Locke, and Equality: Christian Foundations in Locke's Political Thoug 44-82; Larry Siedentop, Democracy in Europe (2000) at 192-8. 38 See Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (2000). This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 395 be able to convince us that when it comes to fundamental decision-making about, for example, which major political party should govern for the next f or five years, or what should be the nation's choice on joining a major intern tional alliance, or whether abortion should be punished by law or not, each ad citizen's qualification to make an informed choice (or, more precisely, the qu fications of each person who cares to go to vote) is as good as that of any othe Indeed, our intuitive acceptance of the one person-one vote system sho through something rather like a reflective equilibrium analysis,39 that we accept the background values that render the democratic system of voting 'fixed point' in our commonly accepted constellation of values. The precise nature of these background values is, of course, a matter tha notoriously divides various theorists of democracy. To say that it is a form equality may be seen as not particularly illuminating because the 'one perso one vote' rule is egalitarian only in a formal and admittedly objectionable sen for one thing, it ignores the unequal resources that various voters have at th disposal to persuade others in a particular way; also, it ignores the uneq intensity of preferences that particular voters espouse. Consequently, the rig ous application of the 'one person one vote' rule may lead to drastically uneq results that offend against the principle of equal concern, substantively und stood: the result of a majority decision (with a one person one vote princip respected) may, for example, lead to an unequal treatment of members of minority.40 But this just goes to show that there is no one canonical standard political equality, and that a 'one person one vote' principle is an egalitarian principle, one among many. It is egalitarian in an undisputed sense that, w employed in the process of decision-making by majority, it 'attempts to give each individual's view the greatest weight possible ... compatible with an equ weight for the views of each of the others'.41 If we intuitively choose the 'o person one vote' principle as regulative of our democratic procedures it is n because of its less egalitarian character than a substantive principle of equal c cern, but because, in a pluralistic community, we would not agree on the com mon criteria as to which outcomes are substantively equal (that is, which express, in their substance, the principle of equal concern).42 We adopt democratic rule on the grounds that are egalitarian through and through, but it is there where our egalitarian consensus ends. It does not detract from the fact that the very adoption of a democratic procedure reveals a prior acceptance of a strongly (though not uncontroversially) egalitarian premise the contours of 39 See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1971) at 19-21. 40 For this argument, see Charles Beitz, Political Equality (1989) at 64. The distinction between equality as expressed in an equal vote and equality revealed in the substance of the decision corresponds to Dworkin's distinction of a 'detached' and 'dependent' interpretations of democracy (focused, respectively, on the input and the output of political decisions), see Dworkin, above n 38 at 185-90. 41 Jeremy Waldron, The Dignity of Legislation (1999) at 148; for a general argument linking the principle of equal consideration of interests with an equal vote, see Thomas Christiano, The Rule of the Many (1996) at 53-71, and, more recently, Thomas Christiano, 'The Authority of Democracy' (2004) 12 Journal of Political Philosophy 266. 42 See similarly Waldron, above n 41 at 162; see also Dworkin, above n 38 at 189. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 396 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 which cannot be further discussed within the confines of thi weighty enough to override the arguments for a non-de government. B. Pure Procedural Democracy? It may be objected that the remarks above apply only to 'politique politisante' rather than a 'politique politisee': that even though, at the level of the general design of a democratic system, its legitimacy is assured by a strong value-based justification, nevertheless at the level of the actual application of the design in everyday political life, the connection between democracy and values cannot be taken for granted. The urge to infuse democracy with values-a democracy-plus conception-can be located at the level of the everyday workings and implementation of the design, rather than the design itself. It is there (so the argument may go) that the danger that democracy will become disconnected from substantive moral value is real, and it is there that the warnings (including those quoted above by John Paul II) against 'a political community independent of ethical principles' maintain their force and validity. To think otherwise would be a sign of naive faith in the self-perpetuating force of the moral values that underlie the choice of a democratic system in the first place: the groundless hope that the values that justify the adoption of democracy would reveal themselves at each 'use' of the system. This would be akin to what John Rawls dubbed 'perfect procedural justice': an institutional system that guarantees that any outcome of the institutional response to a challenge is always and necessarily just, in terms of standards of justice independent of the procedure itself.44 With regard to democracy, it would express a hope that once we put a democratic system in place (justified, as it is, by certain values), each outcome of the democratic game will express those very values. However (the argument might continue), just as in real life we do not have the luxury of 'perfect procedural justice' at work (other than some hypothetical examples invented to illustrate the concept itself, such as-in an example provided by Rawls-a system in which the person who divides a cake will be the last to pick up his slice),45 so in real life we cannot hope for democratic procedures that will always and necessarily give effect to the values that justify the system as a whole. Just as the best that we can hope for in the area of distributive justice is to set up systems of 'imperfect procedural justice' (which maximize the likelihood of achieving procedurally just outcomes), so in the case 43 For an interesting recent attempt to derive (in a qualified way) the principle of equality of voting power from the principle of equal respect for individual autonomy, see Andrei Marmor, 'Authority, Equality and Democracy', University of Southern California Law School Public Policy Research Paper No. 03-15, http://ssrn.com/ abstract=424612, accessed 20 October, 2004. I am grateful to Professor Marmor for his permission to refer to this unpublished paper. 44 See Rawls, above n 39 at 83-7. 45 Ibid at 85. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 397 of the democratic legitimacy of political systems we can hope, at best, for ins tional designs that will maximize, but never guarantee, the achievement comes that are legitimate by virtue of their congruence with the value justified the choice of system in the first place. There is a temptation to give a quick answer to the objection described preceding paragraph, which should be resisted. The temptation is to app the concept of 'pure procedural justice', which is different from the perf imperfect concepts in that it dispenses altogether with outcome-based crit justice: pure procedural justice obtains whenever the correct procedure is s adhered to (as in sports or gambling, in which we do not have any outc based criteria to judge whether the result is just). In contrast, perfect and fect variants of justice use outcome-based criteria, and the only differe between imperfect and perfect justice is that the latter guarantees, where former merely maximizes, the congruence of the outcome with our stand justice. The quick response that I have in mind (but eventually reject) wo to suggest that the problems raised by democracy are more akin to the problk tique of pure procedural justice than to that of (im)perfect procedural jus that the only democratic game in town is procedural and we should not c ourselves with the 'fit' between the outcome of a democratic game and outcome-based standards of democracy, but only with the compliance of p (including legislative) procedures with purely procedural rules. This temptation, as I said, should be resisted: the 'answer' provided he decidedly too quick. Even in Rawls' initial introduction of the three-way d between forms of procedural justice, serious doubts can be raised about 'pure' manifestation: do we really refer to the outcomes of sports compe or gambling as 'just' merely because they comply with the rules of proce To my (admittedly, non-native-English) ear, such a characterization is o place in such situations; the conferral of the status of 'justice' in these ca contrary to the semantic intuition many of us have. This would suggest th language of procedural justice is always and necessarily a reflection of th ness of the outcome.46 This impression is only strengthened upon consid of the problems of democratic legitimacy. To say that, once a democratic is in place, any outcome will be, by definition, democratic because we d have an independent outcome-based notion of democratic legitimacy see contrary to our intuitions. Rather, the opposite is true: we feel that if the de cratic majority, in accordance with a democratic procedure, were to (for example) deprive members of an ethnic minority of their fundamental rights, then the outcome would be illegitimate because contrary to the foundational values of democracy itself. So we do have criteria of a democratically legitimate outcome after all; if we support democracy it is not because we believe that by 46 For more on this, see Wojciech Sadurski, 'Social Justice and Legal Justice' (1984) 3 Law and Philosophy 329 at 346-53. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 398 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 definition anything that such a system produces is legitim we believe that a democracy, more than any other system ment of values that we endorse. It is not by virtue of a defin of legitimacy with the scrupulous observance of procedu through our real-life experiences of how different system that we may endorse democracy: to do so merely by defi weak and unconvincing. Thus, the easy way out of invoking pure procedural ju to us, meaning that the best we can do is to uphold dem similar to imperfect procedural justice: a system that m ment of democracy's foundational values, although it fa teeing that each and every instance of a democratic pro reflect those values. The distinction between 'politique p tique politisee' therefore stands, and the fear that a poli render itself 'independent of ethical principles' cannot b appears, by a general appeal to the ethical principles fou cracy itself. So we need to think a little harder about what the oppo plus would look like, and what dangers may accompany independent of ethical principles'. There are two main wa nection of democracy from moral values can possibly be and reflection upon these two negative scenarios may brin ive idea of what democracy-plus might be. The first wa connection could take place may be understood at the le of political actors in a democracy (both voters and their parliamentary assemblies): if their decisions are motivat considerations but by some other grounds deemed antith of democracy with values. Let us call this aspect 'motiva manner in which such a disconnection may be imagined sions acquire validity solely by virtue of being adopted in way, regardless of the degree of congruency between th foundational values of democracy. This, as we have seen, would be a sign of adopting a 'pure procedural justice'-like approach to democracy, and seems unsatisfactory as it ignores the fact that we construct democratic legitimacy in a way more akin to imperfect procedural justice. The gap between perfect and imperfect justice raises the spectre of decisions that are procedurally correct and based on a system that, by and large, maximizes the attainment of democracy's foundational values but that may, in particular instances, be inconsistent with those values. Let us call this dimension 'constitutional' (for reasons that will become obvious later). These two examples of apparent disconnection of democracy from values should be kept apart, because they generate different problems for the issue of democratic legitimacy in the face of society's value pluralism. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 399 C. Values at the Motivational Level The first level at which we may (theoretically) perceive and deplore 'value-free democracy' is that of the motivations of voters and their representatives. Here short aside is in order: for the purposes of democratic theory as discussed here, the distinction between individual citizens and political actors, such as the members of legislative bodies, is irrelevant: we must assume a full continuity between the motivations, intentions, preferences, etc., of the individual voters and their representatives in parliament (a point to which I will refer below as the 'continuity thesis'). Of course, we know that this assumption is naive and not very realistic, but as a matter of a normative democratic theory it does not make any difference whether we consider the motivations of the institutional actors or of individual citizens. Or, to put it differently, a citizen qua voter is also a polit ical institution, and only as such is considered relevant for the purposes o democratic theory.47 At this motivational level, the separation of democracy from values can be dis cerned in the reliance of voters and their representatives upon their interest rather than values and ideals. Democracy is eroded of values, it can be said, when public decisions are motivated by the calculus of interests rather than by ideals, and when the 'input' to political decision-making consists of our own per ceptions of our interests rather than ideals about the public good. To take an example, if my motivation in voting for a particular taxation scheme (or voting for a party on the basis of its taxation programme) is guided only by the ques tion: 'Which of the alternative tax schemes will be the best for me?', then this results in a deplorably value-free democratic process because the right question should have been: 'Which of the alternative tax schemes best corresponds to a defensible idea of justice in taxation?' This particular example shows, incidentally, that a 'motivational' understanding of the democracy-plus claim is immune to the possible charge that it adopts an illiberal stance in the controversy between perfectionism and anti-perfectionism, in the context of a debate over the proper limits of state action in enforcing moral values. 'Democracy-plus', in this version, may be but need not be illiberally perfectionistic. If perfectionism is understood in a broad, and not necessarily illiberal, way, as the proposition that the role of the state includes the stron commitment to personal autonomy (which requires a high degree of respect fo individual choices of ways of life and which is well captured by the 'harm principle'),48 then the democracy-plus' call for acting on values rather than on inter ests is perfectionistic but in a non-objectionable manner-from the libera standpoint at least. It may simply mean nothing more than that a polity shoul 47 On this last point, see Christopher L. Eisgruber, Constitutional Self-Government (2001) at 50; Bruce Ackerman, We The People: Foundations (1991): 232-43 and 297-314. 4 For such a 'perfectionistic' understanding of autonomy and of the harm principle, see Joeph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (1986) at 412-20; see also, generally, Vinit Haksar, Liberty, Equality, and Perfectionism (1979). This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 400 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 aim at the implementation of some notions of the social accommodation of particular interests should be informed of justice. If, however, perfectionism is taken to mean t enforce some ideals of private morality that express som of individual virtue (i.e., that the state should identify an superior ideals of human excellence),49 there is nothing in ues rather than on interests (whatever it may mean, as wi that creates a necessary bias in this direction within democracy-plus. The demand, for example, that in the debate on redistribution through taxation we should be guided by our ideals of public good rather than by our particular interests is evidently not illiberally perfectionistic: it takes no stand in the dispute about the role of the law in shaping private morality (the notion of 'the good' as contrasted to 'the right', in Rawls's parlance) of the citizens. But the continuity thesis, suggested in the first paragraph of the present section, can be challenged in a way that resonates with the debates concerning 'perfectionism', that is, by appeal to the notion of neutrality of legislation towards competing moral conceptions. It can be claimed that, even if we adopt the ideal of 'moral neutrality' of the state, and attempt to discern the indicia of this neutrality in the motivations of the legislators, it cannot go all the way down; we must not expect individual voters to be neutral on issues of private morality.50 It is one thing, it may be argued, for the state to attempt to be as neutral as possible on the controversial issues of private morality; it is quite another to expect citizens to reflect such neutrality in their decisions and conduct. While the former ideal may be a useful way of articulating the liberal political ideal, the latter demand (addressed to individuals) can be seen as absurd." This 'absurdity', however, can only arise if we confuse the perspective of individual as a private person and an individual as a citizen-voter. Being 'neutral' in our private capacity on moral issues is just a fancy and somewhat pretentious manner of saying that we are uncertain, or agnostic, about some controversial moral matters. But being neutral when we act in our public capacity as voters has no air of absurdity or confusion: it simply means that we act on a distinction between our notions of private morality and our notions of the public good. Naturally, the distinction itself is controversial and open to challenge, but if we accept that the distinction can be made, then it can be drawn equally well in the mind of an individual voter as in the minds of the legislators, and in consequence relied 49 For this understanding of 'perfectionism' see, inter alia, Carlos Santiago Nino, The Ethics of Human Rights (1991) at 132-6, 142-3; see also Tim Gray, Freedom (1991) at 167. The locus classicus of a liberal rejection of perfectionism is, of course, in Rawls, above n 39 at 325-32, restated in John Rawls, Political Liberalism (1993) at 194-5, 292-5. so While a discussion of that point is beyond the scope of this article, it should be acknowledged that for some liberals, including William Galston and Joseph Raz, even the notion of political neutrality as addressed only to lawmakers is incoherent; see William Galston, Liberal Purposes (1991) at 79-97; Raz, Morality of Freedom at 108-22. For my critique of Raz's criticism of the principle of neutrality see Wojciech Sadurski, Moral Pluralism and Legal Neutrality (1990) at 99-111. " See Jeremy Waldron, Liberal Rights (1993) at 154. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 401 upon by the collective legislator in its law-making. Therefore, the continuity thesis seems immune to this criticism. The distinction between these two types of motivations, interests and values corresponds to a classical debate between adherents of a 'pluralistic' conceptio of democracy and those preferring a Rousseauian one. The former-taking their inspiration from Jeremy Bentham-find it both empirically plausible and norma tively acceptable that people vote on the basis of their interests, and the aggre gate public decision that tries to accommodate those various and divergen preferences is the only matrix of a 'public good' that we can have. The latter, following Jean-Jacques Rousseau, reject interests-based decisions as inappropriat in a democracy; they claim that whoever (whether a voter or a representative) tries to gauge his or her interests as the basis for their decisions, answers the wrong question-the one that should not be addressed in the public forum. Th only relevant question to ask is: 'which of the alternative proposals is most congruent with my view about the public good?' (i.e. which best tracks the idea of general will, in Rousseau's parlance); even though we know, contra Rousseau, that we will encounter fundamental disagreements among members of the soc ety in answering this type of question, it will be a different disagreement from that generated by conflicts of interests. A call for 'democracy-plus', under this account, amounts therefore to a rejec tion of a Benthamite vision and endorsement of a Rousseauian democracy in which people vote on the basis of ideals rather than interests.52 Why would suc a choice provide us with a step towards morally legitimate democracy, in the sense of its infusion with moral values? The best answer I can think of is by linking the interests/values distinction to the liberal principle of legitimacy: the principle that the use of coercive powers against a person can be legitimate only if that person can accept the reasons that stand behind the law or policy that authorizes this coercive use. There is an important strand in liberal thinking tha links legitimacy with the consent of the governed.53 Not the actual consent, o course, because such a requirement would undercut the whole search for the principles of political legitimacy; we would end up with the anarchistic idea tha each individual is bound only by those laws to which he has agreed. But consent hypothetical at least, is needed in order to confer some degree of legitimacy upon the laws which, after all, can never enjoy the unanimous support of all th citizens. In a weak but plausible version, the liberal principle of legitimacy postu lates that only those laws that are based upon arguments to which no member of the society have a rational reason to object can boast political legitimacy, an as such be applied coercively even to those who actually disagree with them. 52 On this contrast, see the excellent discussion in Jeremy Waldron, Liberal Rights (1993) at 392-421; see als Rawls, Political Liberalism, above n 49 at 219-20 (endorsing Rousseau's view of voting as 'ideally expressing ou opinion as to which of the alternatives best advances the common good', and contrasting it with the view th 'people may properly vote their preferences and interests'). 53 See Waldron, above n 51 at 45-50. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 402 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 A contemporary locus classicus of this liberal principle of le Political Liberalism: 'Our exercise of political power is fully prop exercised in accordance with the constitution the essentials of which all citizens as free and equal may reasonably be expected to endorse in the light of principles and ideals acceptable to their common human reason'.'4 Rawls further elaborates upon this conception in his discussion of the concept of 'public reason', that is, publicly recognizable standards of right and wrong. He also suggests that, as a test, we might inquire as to whether a particular argument for a new law belongs to the category of 'public reason' by considering whether it could be used in a written opinion of a supreme court.55 The implication is clear: some arguments, even if actually present in the minds of legislators or policy-makers, are not qualified to figure in the public defence of a law: the law must be defensible in terms that belong to a 'forum of principle' rather than an arena of political bargains and plays of naked interest. This last point suggests that the liberal principle of legitimacy operates, more often than not, in a negative (or weak) fashion, namely, to discard illegitimate laws:56 a law cannot claim any legitimacy towards me if it is based upon arguments and reasons that I have no reason to accept. For instance, if the best (or the most plausible) justification that can be given for a law is in terms of a religious sectarian creed, and I happen not to espouse that creed, then I have no rational reason to recognize the law as legitimate. Or if the law is based upon an argument that casts me out from the political community (for example, an argument that considers my racial group as inherently inferior to other groups), then there is no moral reason why I should recognize this law as legitimate: I cannot identify with the reasons that triggered the adoption of this law in the first place. The denial of legitimacy to such a law is based on the view that there must be some connection between the law and myself qua subject of the law-a connection that establishes some rational reasons to identify the good for myself in the law. The connection must be between the substance of the law and the preferences, desires, convictions or interests of each individual subjected to it. If, even under rational examination, no such connection can be detected, then I have no reasons to accept the law as legitimate. If, however, I disagree with the wisdom of a given law, but would agree if I examined it rationally that it is based upon arguments that I can recognize as valid, then a necessary condition for its legitimacy has been met. This point has been well expressed by Jeremy Waldron: 'If there is some individual to whom a justification cannot be given, then so far as he is concerned the social order had better be replaced by other arrangements, for the status quo has made out no claim to his allegiance'.57 s4 Rawls, above n 49 at 137. A broader wording of 'the ideal expressed by the principle of legitimacy' is: 'to live politically with others in the light of reasons all might reasonably be expected to endorse', ibid at 243. ss Ibid at 254. 56 As Rawls admits, 'public reason often allows more than one reasonable answer to any particular question', ibid at 240. s7 Waldron, above n 51 at 44, emphases in the original. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 403 As it stands, the formula is fraught with ambiguity: from the fact that a j cation can be given, it does not follow that it will be accepted as framed in te public reason, just as, to return to Rawls's formula, it does not follow fro diagnosis that citizens 'may be expected to endorse' the constitution tha actually endorse it. The actual acceptance requirement would turn the hyp ical consent test into a real consent (a clearly unreasonable requirement) the other hand, the hypothetical acceptance standard makes the test both manipulable and difficult to apply. There is a space between what the citizens can be reasonably expected to accept and what they actually accept, and the liberal principle of legitimacy reflects the tension between these two poles: an insufficient pole of hypothetical, rational consent and an unrealistic pole of an actual (even if only tacit) consent. This tension, however, is not a contradiction, and does not render the liberal principle of legitimacy chimerical-for two reasons. Firstly, the subject matter of the consent is not the wisdom or justness of the law, but only a certification that the reasons that may be rationally supplied for its defence belong to 'public reason': that is, that they are not 'sectarian' but belong to the category of reasons that may properly be cited in defence of a law. Arguably, it is easier to elicit consent that the reasons provided for adopting a law fall into this category than to seek universal agreement with the specific justification of a particular law: the former is a more lenient test than the latter. Secondly, and more importantly, it does not particularly matter that the criterion of acceptance is discerned in a hypothetical rather than a real consent because what we are concerned with is the legitimacy of the law rather than the citizens' duty to obey, and for this reason we may well identify the locus of legitimacy in the eyes of a critical observer rather than in the eyes of the citizens themselves. This distinction, between a critical-observer perspective and that of an actual citizen corresponds to a distinction drawn by Simmons between generic and transactional evaluations in political philosophy: the former correspond to the general moral virtues of political arrangements, the latter, to the specific, actual interactions between individual persons and their polities.58 Here we can content ourselves with the former because our aim is to ground the system's legitimacy (understood as its justification) rather than the obligation of citizens to comply with its directives. Hypothetical consent becomes, then, merely an 'expository device' of a critical observer's reasoning (just as in Rawls, the original position is an expository device of our individual reasoning about justice),59 leading to the conclusion that the law indeed is legitimate (that, in Raz's language, it properly incorporates in its directives the reasons which apply to its subjects). This is perhaps most clearly viewed in the case of Dworkin's conception of legitimacy, based as it is upon 'the model of principle': our institutions are legitimate if they operate within a community that genuinely takes 'integrity' as central to 58 Simmons, above n 28 at 764. But note that Simmons uses different notions of 'justification' and 'legitimacy' from the ones adopted here. 9 Rawls, above n 39 at 21. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 404 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 politics, and which therefore 'expresses a concern by each ciently special, personal, pervasive, and egalitarian to gro tions'.60 At first blush, there is very little room in this principle of legitimacy for any consent by citizens, hypothet the certification of the institutions as legitimate (and of principle- or integrity-based) results from a judgment as under the standards of the group that generated the proper a In these cases, 'the members of a group must by and large about the responsibilities they owe one another',61 including that the group's practices show not only concern but an members'.62 This judgment (that the group treats all wi need not necessarily be actually shared by those who are o coercive action, but, on the other hand, if even the other cannot reasonably attest to the institutions' attitude of tr concern then those institutions lack a threshold condition It can now be seen that the values/interests distinction is a crude proxy for the distinction between those justifications o erly part of public reason, and hence that can be accepted whom they apply (even if, in practice, some will not agree the laws), and, on the other hand, those justifications that ca izens because they violate the liberal test of legitimacy. The f ues versus interests) is not well correlated with the second of law in terms of public reasons versus justifications th expected to accept), and it is the latter distinction that is legitimacy, the main question that has occupied us here. T secondary, and, to the degree that it does not track the latte no special relevance for us. Why would someone have thought that the interests/v important for the legitimacy of law and policy under som principle of legitimacy? The reason might be this: it could best justification for a particular law is that it meets the then if I am not a member of a group X, I have no reason it is enough to articulate this argument in this way to see For one thing, not every interest-based argument must be 'se there may be laws that implement the interests of everyone providing solutions to coordination problems. They will sti of interests but nevertheless they may figure as 'public r justifiable to (almost) everyone. Second, even if a law's ma it implements the interests of group X, as a non-X memb the importance of meeting this group's interests, on the b 60 Dworkin above n 32 at 216. 61 Ibid at 199. 62 Ibid at 200, emphasis in the original. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 405 fairness, compensatory justice, etc. It may be argued, of course, that th best justification for this law is in terms of justice rather than in term interests, but this only serves to illustrate how uncertain and unreliable distinction between interests and values is in the first place. This is confirmed by common sense. When a particular person votes example, for a particular tax scheme which in fact will make her richer, vote on the basis of her interests, or of her sense of justice (she genuinely b that she deserves it), or on the basis of her view about the public good believes that it is the most efficient scheme, which will, incidentally, al her richer)? It is difficult to separate these different justifications fr other, and the most sensible observation would be that, usually, we m public decisions on the basis of a complex mix of such, and other, just tions.63 Matters become even more complicated if the example does not a law that has clear material benefits and costs to the voters (such as a tax scheme), but rather concerns complex moral judgments about the rightness or otherwise of a particular practice, and the law's proper reaction to it. What would it take to vote on the basis of one's 'interests' on issues such as abortion, euthanasia or capital punishment? A 'Benthamite' picture would probably be that a vote based on interests would mean that someone who feels that she is likely to terminate her pregnancy, or terminate her life, or be punished for m der, will vote, respectively, for a liberal regime of abortion and euthanas against the death penalty. But such a preposterous supposition would be obvious travesty of any realistic account, ignoring what we know about w people support or oppose such laws. The subject-matter of these laws sim does not lend itself to an interest-based motivation although, arguably, w think of arguments in favour of them that would not pass the public-reason t In these areas, calls for value-based motivations (and, more broadly, for a enhanced democracy) simply sound redundant. We may generalize this point. A society does not have normativity-free it is, so to speak, normatively saturated. Some subject-matters-most sub matters belonging to the public area-yield individual choices based on v In this sense, a call for a value-based democracy (understood in the first, m tional, sense discussed here) is empty: it is not the case that democracy should be value-free but rather that it cannot be so. That the motivations of citizens and their representatives in taking public decisions will not be free of values is not a real problem: what is, however, real is that they will differ, often fundamentally, 63 Another way of expressing the same thought would be by using the language of a mix of 'personal' and 'external' preferences, the latter being indistinguishable from personal affirmations of the common good. This was nicely expressed in the classic polemic by H.L.A. Hart regarding Ronald Dworkin's theory, based upon the personal/ external preferences distinction; consider Hart's focus on those 'cases where the external preference is favourable to, and so supports, some personal preference or want for some good or advantage or liberty'. Hart further gives the following example: 'Suppose ... the issue is freedom for homosexual relationships, and suppose that ... it was the disinterested external preferences of liberal heterosexuals that homosexuals should have this freedom that tipped the balance against the external preferences of other heterosexuals who would deny this freedom', H.L.A. Hart, 'Between Utility and Rights' (1979) 79 Columbia Law Review 828 at 842, emphasis in the original. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 406 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 as to the choice of values. This is therefore a 'problem' of m not of value-free democracy. The warnings of the adherent against 'a political community ... independent of ethical prin either very weak, or they are a proxy for a warning against pendent of the right ethical principles'. The very weak interpre a warning against moral indifference or apathy: against citiz sentatives ignoring all moral values when voting on public iss is unfounded, as we have seen, and the warning is for this meaningless. If, however, the warning is understood in the warning against a community independent of the right pr incompatible with the liberal-democratic order that attempts law for people who differ greatly over the moral values they The strong interpretation amounts to a plea for a polity that en the strongly 'perfectionist' manner identified earlier in the arti community that coercively imposes ideals of individual goo those who do not necessarily share them. D. Values at the Constitutional Level The second level at which the legitimacy of democratic laws might be seen to be contingent upon their incorporation of the right values is of a different nature. It concerns not the motivations of the decision-makers (voters and legislators alike), but the value-laden limits upon the substance of democratically adopted decisions; it therefore concerns the 'output' rather than the 'input', so to speak. The idea here is that democratic decisions, in order to be legitimate, must comply with certain substance-related requirements, or that they cannot transcend certain substance-related constraints. I will call this dimension 'constitutional' for the obvious reason that the identification of the substantive limits that a legislator is not permitted to overstep is widely seen to be one of the main functions of constitutions, and in particular of constitutional charters of rights. I will be brief in discussing this aspect of democratic legitimacy-not because it is unimportant but because it has been dealt with so expansively in the literature in constitutional theory. For my present purposes, it is important only to indicate that this second dimension of the 'democracy-plus' raises different problems in the face of moral pluralism than the first, 'motivational' dimension. The issue here is not so much that a fear of moral indifference or apathy is generally unfounded (as was the case with the motivational dimension) but rather that, in the process of the articulation of the meaning of vague constitutional pronouncements, actual moral disagreement over moral values is merely replicated rather than deflated. We may well accept, as a starting point, that the legitimate exercise of authority in a democratic state requires us to assume that there are some limits to what the authorities can decide. Indeed, the acceptance of the principle of respect for human rights itself necessarily means that there are This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 407 substantive limits to what authorities can do to individuals. (There may also other implications of the human rights principle: for example, that there some opportunities that must be provided to citizens, and the language opportunity does not translate easily into the language of limits, except trivia However, human rights include also, amongst other things but necessarily, t idea of limits). The 'problem' is that, faced with moral disagreement in socie even if the constitution is accepted consensually (which is a presupposition adopted only for the sake of argument), the actual articulation of the gene constitutional rights translates the general moral disagreement into a disagr ment as to whether a particular authoritative directive transcends the limi imposed by the constitution. This is not the weak observation that, at the margins, people will disagre about the specific 'penumbra' of a particular vague concept implicated in vario constitutional rights. Rather, it is that the disagreement will often be fundamental and central to the meaning of a right-as-limit. For example, whether freed of speech mandates or prohibits limits on paid political advertisements, whether the right against discrimination prohibits, permits or mandates affirmat action in university admissions, or whether the right to life requires or prohibits assistance in terminating the life of a terminally ill patient on demand-the and a myriad other controversies can easily be understood in terms of consti tional rights but our disagreements in the interpretation of these constitutio rights will simply replicate the prior disagreement over the moral issues t these rights were supposed to resolve. We will not only disagree over whethe proposed law transcends a substantive limit imposed by a constitutional rig but, even more fundamentally, over what interpretation of a right constitut limit on the exercise of state authority in the first place. Is a ban on euthanas limit on what can be done to a person (with the subsequent discussion abou where exactly this limit lies), or is a legal opportunity of terminating one's with the help of a doctor a limit on what can be prohibited and enforced aga a person? The answers, of course, will be a direct reflection of prior and mo fundamental moral disagreement. Thus, while we may well all agree that the should be some limits to what the state can do to individuals, once we start debating what constitutes a limit, not to mention where the limits should properly lie, the constitutional pronouncements of rights will turn out to be singularly unhelpful.64 This is not to say that rights provisions are irrelevant, or without significance. On the contrary, we know that they play a very significant role politically in providing, in various legal systems, judicial or non-judicial bodies with the grounds for decisions that may invalidate, or re-interpret, the laws adopted by legislatures. There is, however, no reason to adopt a position of institutional fetishism, and to assume that a constitutionally identified institution that has the power to 64 More on this, in my 'Judicial Review and the Protection of Constitutional Rights' (2002) 22 OJLS 275 at 294-6. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 408 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 26 displace the choices of other bodies with its own is, eo ipso, ' tion of the meaning of a controversial constitutional pro greement between two bodies, for example between a parliament and a constitutional (or a supreme) court (or to be more precise, between the majorities of these collective bodies), will more often than not merely reflect a moral disagreement existing in the society as a whole about what, in terms of a vague constitutional provision, constitutes a limit on state action, and where that limit should properly lie. The power of such an extra-parliamentary body to pronounce on the decisions of the parliament simply adds one step to the constitutionally prescribed procedure that has to be followed in order for the decision to be final and legitimate; however, it remains a procedure-based legitimacy, not a value-based one. The statute as corrected in a process of judicial review is not necessarily more within the limits defined by constitutional rights than a statute without such a correction, but the review does make a difference in terms of what counts as a legitimate procedure for the issuing of legal directives. As a judge of the US Supreme Court famously observed: 'We are not final because we are infallible, but we are infallible only because we are final'.65 The conferral on a particular institution of the power to strike down laws on the basis of their (alleged) inconsistency with constitutional rights is a matter of institutional fiat which adds (rightly or wrongly-this is beyond the scope of this article) one additional step to the correct procedure to be followed. The decisions that emerge from such a procedure acquire democratic legitimacy, just as those that issue from a procedure where no such possibility of review exists, acquire democratic legitimacy. There may be good substantive, political arguments related to the institutional competence of various organs for creating or removing such a power-but the argument about enhancing legitimacy by injecting the right values into the decision is not one of them. 'Democracy-plus' cannot build upon the notion of substantive, value-based constitutional limits on democratic procedures. 3. Conclusions The upshot of the second part of the article may seem disappointing and haps upsetting. It seems to go against the current popular disenchantment purely 'procedural' democracy which, as the experience of the twentieth cen shows, is not a panacea for all social ills, and often lacks sufficient self-def mechanisms against those who would use democratic procedures to pu inhuman, oppressive and discriminatory goals-and demolish democratic in tutions in the process. But such a reading of my conclusions would be un ranted: I do not call for indifference as to 'values' and for exclusive concern with the proper 'procedures'. If anything, my conclusion is the opposite: that our 65 Brown v Allen, 344 US 443, 540 (1953) (Jackson J, concurring). It should be noted, however, that Justice Jackson made this remark not in the context of the Supreme Court striking down a congressional act, but in the context of reversing a state court's decision. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms SUMMER 2006 Law's Legitimacy and 'Democracy-Plus' 409 values are normally and routinely engaged with democratic procedures, a scepticism about purely procedural democracy can be properly read as a pointment that a particular democratic system gives effect to some value than our own. This sense of disappointment is hard to reconcile with the ance of moral pluralism and disagreement as a pervasive, persistent and si ant feature of contemporary societies. Disappointment of this sort, in particular, should not lead one to deny macy to laws that have been adopted in accordance with proper democrat cedures. This, however, is not a recipe for blind obedience to democrati adopted laws; as I argued in the first part of this article, each individual necessarily obliged to comply with every legitimate law. The disconnect of legitimacy from the duty to obey-a disconnection advanced for reas discussed earlier-has the consequence of deflating the apparent drama of to do about laws adopted in a procedurally correct manner in a democra yet which strike us as morally wrong. A democratic and liberal legal syste and should provide room for disobedience to legitimate law, but this ques beyond the scope of this article: what is important is that a finding that law is legitimate does not necessarily lead to the conclusion that it mus always complied with by those who disagree with it. However, we need guage in which to express the combination of recognition of legitimacy refusal to obey on moral grounds, and if we were to incorporate the 'right' va into our test for the legitimacy of law, then this possibility would no longer This content downloaded from 147.251.160.163 on Wed, 04 Oct 2017 07:13:46 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms