I ■ ■ THE JUDGE IN A DEMOCRACY Aharon Barak ■ . ■ PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS PRINCETON AND OXfORD 84 CHAfTER TWO Chicago). The laws of a people should be interpreted on the basis of tlic assumption thar it wants to continue to exist. Civil rights derive from the existence of the State, and they should not be made into a spade with which to bury it.14* / Similarly, human rights should not be sacftficcd on the altar of the state. After all, human rights arc natural rights that precede the state. Indeed, human rights protections require preservation of the sociopolitical framework, which in turn is based on recognition of the need to protect human rignts. Both the needs of the state and human rights are part of <«ie constitutional structure that simultaneously provides for human rights and allows them to be limited. A unique feature of dernocracy is that the scope and limits of human rights derive from a common source. Justice Dickson of the Canadian Supreme Court nicely noted this peculiar underpinning of democracy with the following comment about Canada's limitation fj/rmula: "The underlying values and principles of a free and democratic society arc the genesis of the rights and freedoms guar/ntccd by (he Charter and the ultimate standard against which/ a limit on a right or freedom must be shown, despite its/ffect, to be reasonable and demonstrably justified."1*0 This is the constitutional dialectic. Human rights and the limitations on them derive from (he same source, and they reflect the same values/* Human rights can be limited, but there arc limits to the linotations. The role of the judge in a democracy is to preserve both/of these limitations. Judges must ensure the security and existence of the state as well as the realization of human rights*, judges must determine and protect the integrity of the proper balance, HV E.A. 2/84. Neimau t>. Chairman afCtnt. Elections Cemm. far f.lrMinh Knasst, 39(2) Pli. 225. 310 (citation omit(cd) (English translation available at \» YvW.COU n. gov. il). "■ Tlx Qfittn r. Oakes^ \ 1986) S.C.R. 103, 136. '•' See Wcinrib. supra p. vi*, note 34 at 127-28. ■ PROTECTING THE CONSTITUTION AND DEMOCRACY 85 Human Dignity ■ Most central of all human rights is the right to dignity1" It is the source from which all other human rights arc derived. Dignit)' unites the other human rights into a whole.153 It also constitutes a right in itself and is recognizee! as such in several constitutions.154 The right of dignity reflects the ''recognition that a human being is a free agent, who develops hi? body and mind as ■ See Edwin] | Ebcilc, Dignity and Liberty. Constitutional Visions in Germany and the United States 1 (2002); The Omeept of Human liignity in Human Rights Discourse (David Krctzmer and Eckart Klein eds., 2002); Human Dignity: This Century and the Next 3-97 (Rubin Gotcsky and Ervin Laszlo cds., 1970); Izhak Englard, "Human Dignity From Antiquity to Modern Israel's ("oimitutioiul Framework," 21 Cardoza L Rer. 1903 (2000); GP. Reicher, -Human Dignity as a Constiwtional Value," 22 UM'. Ont L ÄfF. 171, 171 (1984) ("No p. Canada [\999] 1 S C.B. 497. 507(Cín.). '" Sff Griswrtd * Cenntttitut, 381 US 479,484 (1965) rlSJpeeific guarantee m The Bill of Rights have penumbra«, formed by emanations from those guarantee* thai help give them lite and substance"). w Sir NiuWGIjzct, "Toward an Imperial judiciary?" ř*t>. /mí.. Fall 1975. ľ 104.122. PROTECTING THB CONSTITUTION AND DEMOCRACY 89 change. ° Ido not claim that the court is always the most effective branch for the resolution of disputes. My claim is much more limited: I claim that the court has an important role in bridging the gap between law and society and in protecting the fundaiTtcntal values of democracy, with human rights at the center. The Role of the Judge as Creator of the Cfmmon Imw Within ihc field of common law, almost a/ Sr. Tr 1,82 (K.B. 1772). •* Id. at 79. ijjH !*ij ■& ' Í.-Í M ■ ' cl '■ ' v\ i ■ .. . ,'" ''■'.{.. •$*