municated than is said. A very similar function is exhibited by a structure called an 'it{ mm cleft'construction in English, as shown in [20]. I [20] a. It was rover that chased the squirrels. | b it wasn't me who took your money j- Cooperation and implicature In both examples in [20), the speaker can communicate what' he or she believes the listener may already be thinking (i.e. thej foreground entailment). In [20b.] that foreground entailmenf (someone took your money) is being made the shared knowledge in order for the denial of personal responsibility to be made. The utterance in [20b.] can be used to attribute the foreground entail* ment to the listener(s) without actually stating it (for example, ai ]n much of the precec[lng discussion, we have assumed that a possible accusation). It is one more example of more being comj speakers and listeners involved in conversation are generally cooperating with each other. For example, for reference to be successful, it was proposed that collaboration was a necessary factor. In accepting speakers' presuppositions, listeners normally have to assume that a speaker who says 'my car' really does have the car I that is mentioned and isn't trying to mislead the listener. This j sense of cooperation is simply one in which people having a con-i versation are not normally assumed to be trying to confuse, trick, t or withhold relevant information from each other. In most cir-l cumstances, this kind of cooperation is only the starting point for I making sense of what is said. i In the middle of their lunch hour, one woman asks another how f she likes the hamburger she is eating, and receives the answer ■in [1]. [ij A hamburger is a hamburger. I From a purely logical perspective, the reply in [1] seems to have ; no communicative value since it expresses something completely ! obvious. The example in [1] and other apparently pointless [expressions like 'business is business' or 'boys will be boys', are j called tautologies. If they are used in a conversation, clearly the i speaker intends to communicate more than is said. When the listener hears the expression in [1], she first has to ; assume that the speaker is being cooperative and intends to communicate something. That something must be more than just ;what the words mean. It is an additional conveyed meaning, called an implicature. By stating [1], the speaker expects that the SURVEY COOPERATION AND IMPLICATURE listener will be able to work out, on the basis of what is already known, the implicature intended in this context. Given the opportunity to evaluate the hamburger, the speaker of [i] has responded without an evaluation, thus one implicature is that she has no opinion, either good or bad, to express. Depending on other aspects of the context, additional implio atures (for example, the speaker thinks all hamburgers are the same) might be inferred. Implicatures are primary examples of more being communicated than is said, but in order for them to be interpreted, some basic cooperative principle must first be assumed to be in operation. The cooperative principle i;idea that people involved in a conversation will cooperate with leach other. (Of course, the woman in [z] may actually be indicating that she does not want to take part in any cooperative interaction with the stranger.) In most circumstances, the assumption of cooperation is so pervasive that it can be stated as a cooperative principle of conversation and elaborated in four sub-principles, called maxims, as shown in Table 5.1. 11. park bench and a large dog lying on the ground in front of the j bench. A man comes along and sits down on the bench. [z] Man: Does your dog bite? Woman: No. (The man reaches down to pet the dog. The dog bites the man's hand.) Man: Ouch! Hey! You said your dog doesn't bite. Woman: He doesn't. But that's not my dog. One of the problems in this scenario has to do with communica^ tion. Specifically, it seems to be a problem caused by the man'i |' assumption that more was communicated than was said. It isn't; problem with presupposition because the assumption in 'youi | dog' (i.e. the woman has a dog) is true for both speakers. Th( 4' eor er y" problem is the man's assumption that his question 'Does your do{ bite?' and the woman's answer 'No' both apply to the dog in fron The cooperative principle: Make your conversational contribution such as is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you are engaged. The maxims Quantity Consider the following scenario. There is a woman sitting on ai^ Make your contribution as informative as is required (for the current purposes of the exchange). Do not make your contribution more informative than is required. Quality Try to make your contribution one that is true. Do not say what you believe to be false. Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence. Relation Be relevant. Manner Be perspicuous. Avoid obscurity of expression. Avoid ambiguity. Be brief (avoid unnecessary prolixity). iTABLE 5. i The cooperative principle (following Grice x$yj) of them. From the man's perspective, the woman's answer profit is important to recognize these maxims as unstated assump-vides less information than expected. In other words, she mighftions we have in conversations. We assume that people are norm-be expected to provide the information stated in the last line. Olally going to provide an appropriate amount of information course, if she had mentioned this information earlier, the storf(unlike the woman in [2.]); we assume that they are telling the wouldn't be as funny. For the event to be funny, the woman has tltruth, being relevant, and trying to be as clear as they can. Because give less information than is expected. |tnese principles are assumed in normal interaction, speakers The concept of there being an expected amount of information rarely mention them. However, there are certain kinds of expres-provided in conversation is just one aspect of the more generations speakers use to mark that they may be in danger of not fully COOPERATION AND IMPLICATURE adhering to the principles. These kinds of expressions are called hedges. Hedges The importance of the maxim of quality for cooperative interaction in English may be best measured by the number of expressions we use to indicate that what we're saying may not be totally accurate. The initial phrases in ba.-c] and the final phrase in [3d.] are notes to the listener regarding the accuracy of the main statement. [3] a. As far as I know, they're married. b. I may be mistaken, but I thought I saw a wedding ring on her finger. c. I'm not sure if this is right, but I heard it was a secret ceremony in Hawaii. d. He couldn't live without her, I guess. The conversational context for the examples in [3] might be a recent rumor involving a couple known to the speakers. Cautious notes, or hedges, of this type can also be used to show that th< speaker is conscious of the quantity maxim, as in the initial phrase in [4a.-c.], produced in the course of a speaker's account of hei recent vacation. [4] a. As you probably know, I am terrified of bugs. b. So, to cut a long story short, we grabbed our stuff am I ran. c. I won't bore you with all the details, but it was an exciting trip. Markers tied to the expectation of relevance (from the maxim 0 relation) can be found in the middle of speakers' talk when the] say things like 'Oh, by the way' and go on to mention some poten tially unconnected information during a conversation. Speaker also seem to use expressions like 'anyway', or 'well, anyway', t< indicate that they may have drifted into a discussion of some pos sibly non-relevant material and want to stop. Some expression! which may act as hedges on the expectation of relevance an shown as the initial phrases in jja.-c.], from an office meeting. [5] a. I don't know if this is important, but some of the files are missing. b. This may sound like a dumb question, but whose hand writing is this? c. Not to change the subject, but is this related to the budget? The awareness of the expectations of manner may also lead speakers to produce hedges of the type shown in the initial phrases in [6a.-c.], heard during an account of a crash. [6] a. This may be a bit confused, but I remember being in a car. b. I'm not sure if this makes sense, but the car had no lights. c. I don't know if this is clear at all, but I think the other car was reversing. All of these examples of hedges are good indications that the speakers are not only aware of the maxims, but that they want to show that they are trying to observe them. Perhaps such forms also communicate the speakers' concern that their listeners judge them to be cooperative conversational partners. There are, however, some circumstances where speakers may not follow the expectations of the cooperative principle. In courtrooms and classrooms, witnesses and students are often called upon to tell people things which are already well-known to those people (thereby violating the quantity maxim). Such specialized institutional talk is clearly different from conversation. However, even in conversation, a speaker may 'opt out' of the maxim expectations by using expressions like 'No comment' or 'My lips are sealed' in response to a question. An interesting aspect of such expressions is that, although they are typically not 'as informative as is required' in the context, they are naturally interpreted as communicating more than is said (i.e. the speaker knows the answer). This typical reaction (i.e. there must be something 'special' here) of listeners to any apparent violation of the maxims is actually the key to the notion of conversational implicature. 38 SURVEY COOPERATION AND IMPLICATURE 39 Conversational implicature The basic assumption in conversation is that, unless otherwise indicated, the participants are adhering to the cooperative principle and the maxims. In example [7], Dexter may appear to be violating the requirements of the quantity maxim. [7] Charlene: I hope you brought the bread and the cheese. Dexter: Ah, I brought the bread. After hearing Dexter's response in [7], Charlene has to assume that Dexter is cooperating and not totally unaware of the quantity maxim. But he didn't mention the cheese. If he had brought the cheese, he would say so, because he would be adhering to the quantity maxim. He must intend that she infer that what is not mentioned was not brought. In this case, Dexter has conveyec more than he said via a conversational implicature. We can represent the structure of what was said, with b (= bread) and c (= cheese) as in [8]. Using the symbol +> for an impli-cature, we can also represent the additional conveyed meaning. [8] Charlene: b &c c? Dexter: b (+>NOTc) It is important to note that it is speakers who communicate meaning via implicatures and it is listeners who recognize those communicated meanings via inference. The inferences selected an those which will preserve the assumption of cooperation. Generalized conversational implicatures In the case of example [7], particularly as represented in [8], no special background knowledge of the context of utterance is required in order to make the necessary inferences. The same process of calculating the implicature will take place if Doobie asks Mary about inviting her friends Bella (= b) and Cathy (= c) tc a party, as in [9a.], and gets the reply in [9b.]. The context is different from (7], but the general process of identifying the implicature is the same as in [8]. [9] a. Doobie: Did you invite Bella and Cathy? (b & c?) b. Mary: I invited Bella. (fc+>NOTc When no special knowledge is required in the context to calculate the additional conveyed meaning, as in [7] to [9], it is called a generalized conversational implicature. One common example in English involves any phrase with an indefinite article of the type 'a/an X', such as 'a garden' and 'a child' as in [10]. These phrases are typically interpreted according to the generalized conversational implicature that: an X +> not speaker's X. [10] I was sitting in a garden one day. A child looked over the fence. The implicatures in [10], that the garden and the child mentioned are not the speaker's, are calculated on the principle that if the speaker was capable of being more specific (i.e. more informative, following the quantity maxim), then he or she would have said 'my garden' and 'my child'. A number of other generalized conversational implicatures are commonly communicated on the basis of a scale of values and are consequently known as scalar implicatures. Scalar implicatures Certain information is always communicated by choosing a word which expresses one value from a scale of values. This is particularly obvious in terms for expressing quantity, as shown in the scales in [11], where terms are listed from the highest to the lowest value. [11] < all, most, many, some, few> < always, often, sometimes> When producing an utterance, a speaker selects the word from the scale which is the most informative and truthful (quantity and quality) in the circumstances, as in [12]. [iz] I'm studying linguistics and I've completed some of the required courses. By choosing 'some' in [iz], the speaker creates an implicature (+> not all). This is one scalar implicature of uttering [iz]. The basis of scalar implicature is that, when any form in a scale is asserted, the negative of all forms higher on the scale is implicated. The first scale in [11] had 'all', 'most', and 'many', higher SURVEY COOPERATION AND IMPLICATURE than 'some'. Given the definition of scalar implicature, it should follow that, in saying 'some of the required courses', the speaker also creates other implicatures (for example, +> not most, +> not many). If the speaker goes on to describe those linguistics courses as in [13), then we can identify some more scalar implicatures. [13] They're sometimes really interesting. By using 'sometimes' in [13], the speaker communicates, via implicature, the negative of forms higher on the scale of frequency (+> not always,+> not often). There are many scalar implicatures produced by the use of expressions that we may not immediately consider to be part of any scale. For example, the utterance of [14a.] will be interpreted as implicating '+> not certain' as a higher value on the scale of 'likelihood' and [14b:] '+> not must' on a scale of 'obligation' and '+> not frozen' on a scale of 'coldness'. [14] a. It's possible that they were delayed, b. This should be stored in a cool place. One noticeable feature of scalar implicatures is that when speakers correct themselves on some detail, as in [15], they typically cancel one of the scalar implicatures. [15] I got some of this jewelry in Hong Kong—um actually I think I got most of it there. In [15], the speaker initially implicates '+> not most' by saying 'some', but then corrects herself by actually asserting 'most'. That final assertion is still likely to be interpreted, however, with a scalar implicature (+> not all). Particularized conversational implicatures In the preceding examples, the implicatures have been calculated without special knowledge of any particular context. However, most of the time, our conversations take place in very specific con texts in which locally recognized inferences are assumed. Such inferences are required to work out the conveyed meanings which result from particularized conversational implicatures. As an illustra tion, consider example [16], where Tom's response does not appear on the surface to adhere to relevance. (A simply relevant answer would be 'Yes' or 'No'.) [16] Rick: Hey, coming to the wild party tonight? Tom: My parents are visiting. In order to make Tom's response relevant, Rick has to draw on some assumed knowledge that one college student in this setting expects another to have. Tom will be spending that evening with his parents, and time spent with parents is quiet (consequently +> Tom not at party). Because they are by far the most common, particularized conversational implicatures are typically just called implicatures. A further example, in which the speaker appears not to adhere to (i.e. to 'flout') the maxim of manner, is presented in [17]. [17] Ann: Where are you going with the dog? Sam: TotheV-E-T. In the local context of these speakers, the dog is known to recognize the word 'vet', and to hate being taken there, so Sam produces a more elaborate, spelled out (i.e. less brief) version of his message, implicating that he doesn't want the dog to know the answer to the question just asked. In [18], Leila has just walked into Mary's office and noticed all the work on her desk. Mary's response seems to flout the maxim of relevance. [18] Leila: Whoa! Has your boss gone crazy? Mary: Let's go get some coffee. In order to preserve the assumption of cooperation, Leila will have to infer some local reason (for example, the boss may be :nearby) why Mary makes an apparently non-relevant remark. The implicature here is essentially that Mary cannot answer the ^question in that context. r In addition to these fairly prosaic examples of implicatures, there are other more entertaining examples, as in [19] and [20], where the responses initially appear to flout relevance. I [19] Bert: Do you like ice-cream? I Ernie: Is the Pope Catholic? SURVEY COOPERATION AND IMPLICATURE ciple or the maxims. They don't have to occur in conversation, and they don't depend on special contexts for their interpretation. .J. Not unlike lexical presuppositions, conventional implicatures are associated with specific words and result in additional conveyed meanings when those words are used. The English conjunction 'but' is one of these words. The interpretation of any utterance of what is communicated and not said, speakers can alwayfmy choosing white (=q). deny that they intended to communicate such meaning; Conversational implicatures are deniable. They can be explicitly denied (or alternatively, reinforced) in different ways. To take simple example, there is a standard implicature associated witl stating a number, that the speaker means only that number, aj shown in [21]. [21] You have won five dollars! (+> ONLY five) implicatures can be calculated, suspended, cancelled, and reinforced. None of these properties apply to conventional implicatures. J20] Bert: Do vegetarians eat hamburgers? Ernie: Do chickens have lips? In [19], Ernie's response does not provide a 'yes' or 'no' answer. Bert must assume that Ernie is being cooperative, so he considers Ernie's 'Pope' question and clearly the answer is 'Yes'. So, the answer is known, but the nature of Ernie's response also implicates that the answer to the question was 'Obviously, yes!'. An dditional conveyed meaning in such a case is that, because thej conventional implicatures are not based on the cooperative prin Conventional implicatures In contrast to all the conversational implicatures discussed so far, answer was so obvious, the question did not need to be asked Example [20] provides the same type of inferencing with a answer 'Of course not!' as part of the implicature. Properties of conversational implicatures So far, all the implicatures we have considered have been situate«j°f the type p but q will be based on the conjunction p & q pi within conversation, with the inferences being made by peoplp3" implicature of 'contrast' between the information in p and who hear the utterances and attempt to maintain the assumption of cooperative interaction. Because these implicatures are parB |the information in q. In [23], the fact that 'Mary suggested black'. p) is contrasted, via the conventional implicature of 'but', with U3] Mary suggested black, but I chose white, b. p & q (+> p is in contrast to q) Other English words such as 'even' and 'yet' also have conventional implicatures. When 'even' is included in any sentence describing an event, there is an implicature of 'contrary to expectation'. Thus, in [24] there are two events reported (i.e. John's coming and John's helping) with the conventional implicature of As shown in [22], however, it is quite easy for a speaker to sullen'adding * 'contrary to expectation' interpretat.on of those pend the implicature (+> only) using the expression 'at leasf " [22a.], or to cancel the implicature by adding further inform^ [24] a. Even John came to the party. tion, often following the expression 'in fact' [22b.], or to reinforcjj the implicature with additional information, as in [22c.]. [22] a. You've won at least five dollars! b. You've won five dollars, in fact, you've won ten! c. You've won five dollars, that's four more than one! We have already noted with many of the previous exampl that implicatures can be calculated by the listeners via inferenct [25] a. Dennis isn't here yet. In terms of their defining properties, then, conversation b. He even helped tidy up afterwards. The conventional implicature of 'yet' is that the present situation is expected to be different, or perhaps the opposite, at a later time. In uttering the statement in [25a.], the speaker produces an implicature that she expects the statement 'Dennis is here' (= p) to be true later, as indicated in [25b.]. b. NOT p is true (=NOTp) (+> p expected to be true later) 44 SURVEY COOPERATION AND IMPLICATURE 45 ft It may be possible to treat the so-called different 'meanings' ol 'and' in English (discussed in Chapter i) as instances of conventional implicative in different structures. When two statements containing static information are joined by 'and', as in [26a.], the implicature is simply 'in addition' or 'plus'. When the two statements contain dynamic, action-related information, as in [26b.], the implicature of 'and' is 'and then' indicating sequence. [26] a. Yesterday, Mary was happy and ready to work. (p &cq,+>pplusq) b. She put on her clothes and left the house. (p & q after p) Because of the different implicatures, the two parts of [26a.] cat observation that utterances perform actions, generally known ai 'speech acts'. 6 Speech acts and events In attempting to express themselves, people do not only produce utterances containing grammatical structures and words, they be reversed with little difference in meaning, but there is a bij perform actions via those utterances. If you work in a situation Sirhere a boss has a great deal of power, then the boss's utterance jbf the expression in [1] is more than just a statement. [1] You're fired. change in meaning if the two parts of [26b.] are reversed. For many linguists, the notion of 'implicature' is one of th central concepts in pragmatics. An implicature is certainly i prime example of more being communicated than is said. Fof those same linguists, another central concept in pragmatics is th< The utterance in [1] can be used to perform the act of ending your employment. However, the actions performed by utterances do snot have to be as dramatic or as unpleasant as in [1]. The action tan be quite pleasant, as in the compliment performed by [2a.], jthe acknowledgement of thanks in [2b.], or the expression of surprise in [2c.]. [2] a. You're so delicious, b. You're welcome. y c. You're crazy! Actions performed via utterances are generally called speech acts and, in English, are commonly given more specific labels, such as apology, complaint, compliment, invitation, promise, or request. These descriptive terms for different kinds of speech acts apply to the speaker's communicative intention in producing an utterance. The speaker normally expects that his or her communicative intention will be recognized by the hearer. Both speaker and shearer are usually helped in this process by the circumstances surrounding the utterance. These circumstances, including other utterances, are called the speech event. In many ways, it is the SURVEY SPEECH ACTS AND EVENTS