1 Ústav religionistiky Jonathan Z. Smith: Adde Parvum Parvo Magnus Acervus Erit, in: Jonathan Z. Smith, Map is not Territory, The University of Chicago Press: Chicago 1993, s. 240 - 264 FRVŠ 1890/2005 Téma: Religionistická klasifikace: monotetický a polytetický Theprocess of comparison is a fundamental characteristic of human intelligence. Whether revealed in the logical grouping of classes, in poetic similes, in mimesis, or other like activities-comparison, the bringing together of two or more objects for the purpose of noting either similarity or dissimilarity, is the omnipresent substructure of human thought. Without it, we could not speak, perceive, learn, or reason. Instances of comparison are presumably as old as mankind itself and may be found in our earliest literary documents. It is unfortunate that relatively little work has been done on the history of the use of comparison in scholarship and that deeper questions of method and the underlying philosophical implications of comparison have been ignored by many disciplines including History of Religions. That comparison has, at times, led us astray there can be no doubt; that comparison remains the method of scholarship is likewise beyond question. S Samuel Butler recorded in his notebook: "Though analogy is often misleading, it is the least misleading thing we have." Robert Redfield, in his important essay, "Primitive World View," suggested that a world view of any people consisted essentially of two pairs of binary oppositions: MAN/NOTMAN and WE/THEY. Both of these pairs imply comparison; it is the latter which underlies most forms of mltllral comparisol1. When one encounters another, a place must be found for the other within or without one's cosmos. Four specifications of the WE/THEY duality have been employed: (1) They are LIKE-US, (2) They are NOT-LIKE-US, (3) They are TOOMUCH-LIKE-US (Robert Frost's "Good fences make good neighbors"), or (4) We are NOTLIKE-THEY (expressions and polemics concerning "uniqueness"). This primary sense of comparison depends upon the living contact between two peoples, whether this contact be through travel, invasion, or trade. It is the attempt to "place" one another. A second major class of comparison is that of historical comparison, whether of the popular example type or in more complex hermeneutic discussions by scientific and philosophical historians. Here the question is not communication between two living representatives of differing cultures and their mutual positioning, but between the present and the past. The question has become: are the individuals and cultures of the past LIKE-US or NOT-LIKE-US? If they were LIKE-US why should we want to know about them? If they were NOT-LIKE-US how can they be comprehended? These (questions are to the fore in Dilthey's description of the hermeneutic task: "Interpretation would be impossible if [past] expressions of life were completely strange. It would be unnecessary if nothing strange were in them. It lies, therefore, between these two extremes." History in general and historical study of religion in particular, is caught between these tensions. Comparison, the existence of similarity, is the inescapable presupposition of historical research. On the one hand the 2 historian recognizes the truth of Toynbee's remark that "this word 'unique' is a negative term signifying what is mentally inapprehensible. The absolutely unique is, by definition, indescribable." On the other hand, he recognizes that he is dealing with a subject so value laden (whether it be an individual's biography or religion) as to elicit from his subject a selfconsciousness of importance and uniqueness. In a shrewd passage, which I recall each time I hear the historian of religions insist on the sui generis character of religions, William James put the matter with precision: "The first thing the intellect docs with an object is to class it along with something else. But any object that is infinitely important to us and awakens our devotion feels to us also as if it must be sui generis and unique. Probably a crab would be filled with a sense of personal outrage if it could hear us class it without ado or apology as a crustacean, and thus dispose of it. 'I am no such thing,' it would say: 'I am myself, myself alone.'" This tension between the subject's sense of the unique and the methodological requirement of the analogous generates both the excitement and the problematics of historical research. The third great class of comparison is, in part, a combination of the first two. It is, at one and the same time, both observation and theory. It is the noting of similarity (LIKE-US) and the accounting for this similarity in terms of a process of assimilation, diffusion, ` (i.e., they are LIKE-US because they ARE-US, they have COME-FROM-US, we are RELATEDTO-THEIR). It is to introduce a temporal, historical framework with high value placed on priority in time. While not always displaying the hostility of early Christian theories of "demonic plagiarism," there is a clear sense of higher value and authenticity attached to the source and a sense of second-handedness, of imitation, and even of fraud attached to the alleged borrower. Furthermore, there is frequently a strong sense of in- and out-groups, of peoples from whom it is all right to have borrowed and peoples from whom one ought not. The pedigree, being "of good stock," is all-important. Such diffusionist theories have remained the prime mode of accounting for similarity since the writings of Herodotus. The fourth great class of comparison is comparison as a hermeneutic device. Here the meaning and function of a particular motif, symbol, or custom in one culture may be used as a key to interpret a similar motif, symbol, or custom in another culture by moving from what is known to what is unknown. The rationale given for this procedure may take three forms: an atemporal argument that both elements are manifestations of a common archetype or reflections of the psychic unity of mankind; a broadly temporal argument for the validity of comparing similar stages of human development (e.g., the comparisons between the Australian aborigines and certain Paleolithic religious structures); or an argument that presupposes some temporal sequence (e.g., the hermeneutic use of the notion of survivals). It will be my contention in this paper that these four great classes of comparison, when applied to religious and cultural data, have involved four modes or styles of comparison; the ethnographic, the encyclopedic, the morphological, and the evolutionary. The remainder of this paper will be concerned with a brief characterization, history, and evaluation of these in the belief that most of the procedures and specific instances of comparison may best be understood as an application of one or more of these styles or modes. THE ETHNOGRAPHIC 3 The earliest extant example of comparative religions occurs in the well-known fragment of Xenophanes (ca. 570-475 B.C.); "The Ethiopians say that their gods are snub nosed and black; the Thracians say that their gods have light blue eyes and red hair." However, the text is too brief to permit one to determine the sorts of traditions which lie behind this observation or to permit one to elucidate the method of comparison being employed. The development of procedures of comparison between religions is first displayed in the writings of Herodotus (484-424 B.C.) who, in addition to his usual title, Pater historiae, may be accurately termed the Father of Anthropology and the Father of History of Religions. Herodotus sums up the ethnography of the Ionian School of historians, and his work and procedures remain the model for the ethnographic style Central to this enterprise was the use of comparison. As T. Hodgen has noted: "the most significant bequest made by Herodotus to subsequent thought was his use of comparison, and his recognition, even in the fifth century B.C., of some of the problems which have emerged whenever the comparison of cultures has revealed either similarities or differenccs." A hint as to the basis for cultural comparative religion." comparison may be found in Herodotus' report of the reply of the Athenians to the Spartans when they refused to break with the common Greek cause. Here we are given the four criteria Herodotus had for determining a cultural unity: common descent, common language, common religious practices, common customs and world view (VIII.144). It will be the presence of one or more of these features in common that will allow Herodotus to make cross-cultural comparisons. In Ionian ethnography as represented by Herodotus we find histo6a in the most literal sense of the word, "a narrative of what one has learned by inquiry," and it would appear that there was a fixed form of inquiry, a questionnaire, employed by Herodotus in his researches. The topics may be discerned in the stereotyped form Ionian ethnography followed for the presentation of its data. I. The 1,-and: (a) borders, measurement, shape; (b) nature and character of the land; (c) rivers; (d) climate; (e) animals, trees etc. II. People-History and Customs: (a) number of population; (b) their antiquity; (c) their habits (e.g., dress, food); (d) customs (nomoi). The subdivisions of this category may be best illustrated by the Scythian material in Book IV (1) gods (theoi, IV.59); (2) sacrifices ( I V.60); (3) war customs ( IV.64); (4) oracles (V.67); (5) oaths (, IV.70); (6) burial practices and tombs ( 1\'.71); (7) foreign customs (1V.76). III. Wonders and Marlels. What is being collected under these headings for some fifty cultures is basically a set of traveler's impressions. Something other has been encountered, and it is surprising either in its similarity or dissimilarity to what is familiar "back home." In such a context, features, political structures, customs, and religious practices-these are at one and the same time the most ethnically distinct and humanly similar features that would attract the eye of the traveler. Only rarely is the truly unique met and recorded (e.g., "The Magi are indeed a unique race different entirely from the Egyptian priests and indeed from all other men" [1.140]); more often the differences are relativized by means of comparison. 4 This reliance on the traveler's eye relates Herodotus and the Ionian ethnographic tradition to ethnography as it is practiced today. Not only does the outline of topoi look very much like a table of contents for a contemporary field worker's report, but other characteristics are shared as well. Without pressing the point too far (and thus continuing the fallacious tradition in popular works on classics for finding Greek antecedents for contemporary theories such as evolution and atomic structures) there is a marked functionalism to these ancient accounts. As each culture encountered is presented largely in its own terms (the interpretatio graeca notwithstanding), the individual items are given in the complexity of their interrelationships and not excised from their context. They are given as they appear to the observer's vision without apparent analytical mediation. In the case of religious material, it is striking how rarely Herodotus introduces a description of a people's god or their mythology for its own sake. Of the thirteen peoples whose religion is discussed, in only one case, that of the Scythians, do the gods occupy first place in Herodotus's account. In the other twelve, priority is given to cultic institutions, and their gods or theology are only introduced insofar as it is required to comprehend the cult which has been seen by the observer. Thus in the Egyptian material, the fullest presentation of religion in Herodotus and one which clearly derives from his own travel experience, the material is not arranged as in present-day handbooks, by deities, but by animals sacred to the gods or utilized in their cult. The individual gods are only introduced as excurses under the heading of the appropriate animals. The same pattern may be noted in Herodotus's use of myth. He only narrates seven myths, and these he tells with extreme economy. Two of them (the births of Herakles [11.43- 45] and of Pan and Dionysos [II.142146]) are told for their importance in establishing a chronological detail; five are cult aetiologies 111.42, 63, 146; Vl1.26; VIlI.55). Consistently, for Herodotus, it is the descriptions of the cultic institutions as they are seen which calls forth a discussion of the gods and not vice versa. Herodotus's cultural comparisons are likewise dependent upon what happens to have been seen and what catches his fancy: Oaths are taken by these people the same way as by the Greeks except that they make a slight flesh wound in their arms.(1.74) The Lydians have very nearly the same customs as the Greeks except that they do not raise their girls in the same way. (1.94) [The Babylonian's] shoes arc peculiar; not unlike those worn by the Boetians. (1.195) In their dress and mode of living, the Massagetae resemble the Scythians. (1.215) The Thracians, Scyths, Persians, Lydians and almost all other barbarians hold the citizens who practice trades in no less repute than the rest .... These ideas prevail also in Greece, particularly among the Lacedaemonians. Corinth is the place where handicrafts arc least despised. (II.167) The difficulties with these comparisons are the same difficulties encountered in specific cultural ethnography today (as Levi-Strauss has brilliantly argued with respect to Boas and Malinowski). Such comparisons are idiosyncratic, depending upon intuition, a chance association, or the knowledge one happens to have at the moment of another culture. There is nothing systematic to such comparisons, they lack any basis, and so, in the end, they strike us as uninteresting, petty, and unrevealing. In Lévi-Strauss's critique, such comparison "loses 5 the means of distinguishing between the general truths to which it aspires and the trivialities with which it must be satisfied." Finally, the ethnographer is driven to generalizations which are platitudes (such as Herodotus's famous dictum, quoting Pindar, "custom is king over all" [III.38]) or to the tautologies of functionalism. Herodotus has bequeathed to us the rich tradition of culture specific ethnography; he has bequeathed to us also the problems of such a procedure. Whether in Greco-Roman texts or in the more recent arguments concerning Kulturkreislehre, historicism, fieldwork, limited comparison, or functionalism-the ethnographer cannot escape generalization and comparison and thus cannot escape the problem of the basis for such generalization and comparison, its criteria, its .extent, and meaning. THE ENCYCLOPEDIC The ethnographic tradition begun by the Ionian school continues with varying fortune to the present day. In Greco-Roman writers such as Ctesias on the Persians and Indians, Megasthenes on the Indians, Poseidonius on the Celts, Tacitus on the Germans, or the nationalistic ethnologies compiled by figures such as Alexander Polyhistor, the device of presenting a set group of to poi concerning the culture of a specific people remained a major scholarly option. Dependent as it was upon travel and first-hand acquaintance, it flourished in periods of travel and trade and declined in periods of isolation. In the West, with only an occasional pilgrim's iti1lerarilllll as an exception, there is little new ethnography until the Ystoria Alo11galort/m of John of Pian del Carpine in the thirteenth century. From this point on there has been, with few gaps, a relatively unbroken tradition of ethnographies. The encyclopaedic tradition was not limited by external circumstances. Rather than the presentation of topoi for a single culture which has been encountered by the author as was characteristic for the ethnographic mode, the encyclopaedic style offered a topical arrangement of cross-cultural material (arranged either by subject matter or alphabetically) culled from reading.30 It is the style of the "armchair" anthropologist rather than the field worker. The tradition began with Hellanicus in the fifth century. He produced a variety of ethnographies reminding us of the works of the Ionian school (Aegyptiaca, Persica, Scythica) but distinguished from them by being entirely derived from reading other men's works. He also produced a set of general, topical collections with titles such as On Peoples, On the Foundings of Cities and Peoples, and Foreign Customs. If one stream of the encyclopaedic tradition descends from these sort of collections, the other stream focuses on the contents of these collections. The third group of data given in the Ionian scheme was that of wonders. While frequently these take the form of points of interest which the traveler must see, at times they express what is different about a culture, how they are NOT-LIKE-US. Thus Herodotus provides, in 11.35-37, an antipodal account of Egypt: "Not only is the climate different from 6 that of the rest of the world, and the rivers unlike any other rivers, but the people also, in most of their manners and customs, exactly reverse the common practice of mankind." A similar description is given of the Scyths (IV.28). Occasionally other sorts of marvels are narrated (e.g., the Phoenix [II.73]; flying snakes [II. 75], or the ants who dig up gold r III.102, 105]) but Herodotus is careful to insist that he has never seen these things but was "told" about them. With the development of the paradoxographical tradition associated in its origin with the poet Callimachus (fl. 270 B.C.), these materials. began to be collected in works reminiscent of more recent books such as Charles Fort's Book of the Damned or Robert Ripley's series, Believe It or Not. The encyclopaedic tradition became inextricably 'wedded to the quest for the exotic, the marvelous, the anomalous, the strange. Callimachus's worksCostumes of Foreign Peoples, Curiosities Collected All Over the World according to Place as well as those of his descendants - the pseudo-Aristotelian (?), De Mirabilibus, Antigonus of Carystas, Collection of Wonderful Stories, Phlegon of Tralles, On Marvels and Long Lived Peoples - stand in direct relationship to such later works as Frazer's The Golden Bough. The encyclopaedic tradition, fused with paradoxographical and teratological traditions, became cabinets de curiosités, contextless lists of strange things clone by strange peoples in strange lands. Characteristic of this entire tradition is relatively little interest in explicit comparison. The material is NOT-LIKE-US, it is inhuman, monstrous, primitive, exotic. It possesses, by its very nature, no comparability with civilized or cultured men. Nor, with its interest in the unique, does the encyclopaedia compare the data in its lists. They simply cohabit within some category, inviting comparison by their very coexistence; but providing no explicit clues as to how this comparison may be undertaken. The sheer density of the "factual" material presented-whether it be Pliny's claim to have read two thousand books by four hundred and seventy three authors and to have excerpted some twenty thousand items for his Historia Naturalis XXXVII or the even grander enterprise of Frazer-the almost epic quality of the lists tends to dull one's critical faculties. The data are accepted as being overwhelmingly and massively there. Interpretation and comparison are simply not asked for. Similarly it is the aesthetic of the catalogue or list to present largely a surface appearance. Depth, the problematics, are eliminated (much as in a Robbe-Grillet novel) in favor of the "hard" enumeration of things. When one does begin to ask depth questions, when one inquires into the context of the material, the principles of internal order governing the lists, or asks for some evaluation of the significance of the material (other than that it is exotic and hence intrinsically interesting), the surface cracks apart. Franz Steiner, in his important book Taboo, has caught a classic instance in Frazer: "Burial grounds were taboo; and in New Zealand a canoe which had carried a corpse was never afterwards used, but was drawn on shore and painted red. Red was the taboo colour in New Zealand; in Hawaii, Tahiti, Tonga and Samoa it was white. In the Marquesas a man who had slain an enemy was taboo for ten days: he might have no intercourse with his wife and might not meddle with fire; he had to get some one to cook for him. A woman engaged in the preparation of cocoa-nut oil was taboo for five days or more." Extending Steiner's analysis, I would suggest that five different verbal associations make up this extract: (1) General thesisburial grounds are taboo, that is, the place where the corpse was laid. This leads to the 7 example of the New Zealand canoe in which a corpse was laid because it was taboo. (2) This canoe was painted red; this leads to the report, irrelevant to the subject of burial taboos that in New Zealand red is a taboo colour. (3) On the order of the familiar test question, "If I say black, what do you think of?" Frazer continues a chain of association. If red is the taboo color on one Pacific island, white is taboo for four other Pacific islands. (4) Having noted color taboos on Pacific islands, Frazer recalls the taboos on Marquesa, another Pacific island, regarding a man who has slain his enemy. This report, while having nothing to do with colors or burial grounds, has at least the virtue of having something to do with death. (5) One of these Marquesan taboos involves cooking, which leads Frazer to speak of another cooking taboo in some unnamed location (presumably another Pacific island) having to do with the preparation of cooking oil. And so, on and on. After carefully working through a passage like this, which is by no means unique to Frazer or any other encyclopaedist, one can only echo Steiner's conclusion: "This is the rhetoric of association. The more clearly it stands out, the less trustworthy the scholarship of the author appears." The unfortunate link of the use of contextless lists held together by mere surface associations rather than careful, specific, and meaningful comparisons with the interest in exotic content has plagued the encyclopaedic tradition until the present time. Malinowski's charge to his anthropological colleagues likewise remains in force: "We can only plead for the speedy and complete disappearance from the records of fieldwork of the piecemeal items of information, of customs, beliefs and rules of conduct floating in the air. ... With this [disappearance] the theoretical arguments of Anthropology will be able to drop the lengthy litanies of threaded statement which make us anthropologists feel silly and the savage look ridiculous." THE MORPHOLOGICAL In his seminal essay on the sociology of knowledge, Karl Mannheim introduced a valuable distinction which bears directly on the question of the logic of comparison as well as having profound implications for discussions of reductionism. Mannheim distinguished between "right-wing" and "left-wing" methodologies: "Early nineteenth century German conservatism ... and contemporary conservatism too, for that matter, tend to use morphological categories which do not break up the concrete totality of the data of experience, but seek rather to preserve it in all its uniqueness. As opposed to the morphological approach, the analytical approach characteristic of the parties of the left, broke down every concrete totality in order to arrive at smaller, more general, units which might then be recombined through the category of causality or functional integration." Extending Mannheim's observation, the following methodological clusters emerge as possibilities: "Right Wing": Morphological/Synthetic / Structural / Synchronic / Phenomenological. "Left Wing": Evolutionary / Analytic / Functional/Diachronic / Historical. 8 Each cluster has its legitimate types of tasks, questions, and procedures. Reductionism is an inherent danger for either group (although the conservative approach, by its very nature, appears less likely to be reductionistic than the radical; an observation not sufficiently recognized in many discussions of reductionism). A more serious problem arises when, to borrow a pun from a recent anthropological symposium, there is a muddle instead of a model, when elements from the two clusters are carelessly combined. It is this muddle, as I shall discuss below, which produced the dismay with late nineteenth and early twentieth-century use of The Comparative Method. The rise of the "science" of Comparative Religions cannot be separated from nineteenth-century scientific thought in general. When, in 1905, Louis H. Jordan defended the legitimacy of Comparative Religion to claim for itself the title of a "science," he pointed to analogies in the field of Comparative Anatomy and Comparative Philology. It is often forgotten how decisive a role the successes of Comparative Anatomy played in the development of the various comparative disciplines. Beginning with Buffon and continued by his great disciple, Cuvier, and as an independent development the more speculative researches of Goethe and St. Hilaire, the anatomists consistently insisted that comparison was the scientific method. Buffon declared that "comparison was the sovereign key to the discovery of general laws in zoology"; Goethe insisted that "natural history is basically comparison." As is well known, in early literature the term "anthropology" was almost exclusively limited to what is today termed "physical anthropology," and most of the important early cultural anthropologists were themselves medical men (e.g., A. Bastian, D. Livingstone, K. von den Steinen, W. H. R. Rivers, C. G. Seligman, P. Rivet). Thus it is not surprising that Anthropology was swift to adopt the comparative (anatomical) method both fur its treatment of physical and cultural data. Likewise in Linguistics, the second great nourishing stream of the Comparative Religions method, Jacob Grimm, Friedrich Schlegel, and William von Humboldt all confessed themselves to be deeply influenced by Comparative Anatomy. The same was the case for the equally influential philosophical sociologists, A. Comte and H. Spencer. The discipline of Comparative Anatomy in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries underwent two main stages of development: first, the morphological approach; then, the evolutionary. Comparative Religions, naively reflecting this development, was basically an illegitimate and unreflective combination of the older morphological approach to the problems of comparison with the newer evolutionary frame of reference. Linnaeus had proposed that his taxonomy represented a closed immutable system which reflected the world of nature conceived as a fixed order of permanent structures. Goethe, who first coined the word "morphology," while recognizing variability, nevertheless arranged his material serially in a hierarchy of increased organization and complexity. One series illustrated the gradations from, the simplest herb to the most complex tree; another series illustrated the sequence of individual organs within the same plant from cotyledon to leaf to corolla to fruit. In no case was a temporal schema employed. The progression was one of logical-formal sequence, not growth and development In time. Goethe's scheme, despite the claims of some of his later admirers, was never evolutionary; it was a typological series that 9 was fundamentally ahistorical while employing the most complex dialectic between the universal and the particular, between ideal and experience, between idea and appearance, between Being and history. The constellation of terms used by Goethe to describe the status of the Urpflanze ­ it is a concept (Begriff), supersensible, beyond the vicissitudes of time, symbolic, a self-revealed mystery (das offenbare Geheimnis), visible to the mind alone-has led some interpreters to overemphasize the idealistic character of the morphology and to fail to take into account the dialectic between the type and history. The type is by definition ahistorical, yet it stands in a complex relationship to the historical. "Time is governed by the oscillations of a pendulum; the moral and scientific worlds, by oscillations between ideas and experience." This "oscillation" has profound implications for the comparative enterprise. Meditation on concrete plants or animals may reveal the archetype which they manifest; meditation upon the type will reveal the vitality of the individual variations. The morphological enterprise is "to recognize living forms as such, to see in context their visible and tangible parts, to perceive them as manifestations of something within and thus to master them to a certain extent in their wholeness through a concrete vision (Anschauung). (I note parenthetically that this seems closer to what historians of religion mean when they invoke phenomenology than the technical procedures of the philosophical phenomenological movement.) But, as in Plato, the upward path requires the downward for its fulfillment. "The particular always underlies the universal; the universal must forever submit to the particular." Comparison may thus occur between the individual and the archetype; comparison may also occur between analogous members of an atemporal series (X is homologous to Y). In either case, neither temporal nor causal conclusions may be drawn from such comparison, that is, X is simpler than Y, it is logically and formally prior but not necessarily prior in time. In cultural studies, this morphological perspective might be illustrated by J. F. McLennan in 1896, when he advocated the study of the "least-developed races" which he defined as "the lowest and simplest," reminding his readers that "in the science of history old means not old in chronology but in structure." It is massively and masterfully illustrated in Mircea Eliade's Patterns in Comparative Religion. Thus when I read in Eliade his numerous and central references to un systeme coherent behind the various manifestations and hierophanies; when he arranges a series of hierophanies from the most elementary to the most complex; when he insists that this systeme nowhere exists but that the archetypes preexist any particular manifestation, that the systeme "manifest more clearly, more fully and with greater coherence what the hierophanies manifest in an individual, local and successive fashion"-I am reminded of such classic statements of the morphological enterprise as Goethe's letter to Herder (Naples, May 17, 1787). The failure to recognize this ambience has been responsible for significant misinterpretation of the role of history and the status of the patterns in Eliade's work. Such a morphology docs have one crucial presupposition, the scientific analogue to which was clearly stated by Kant in his Critique of Judgement: "All such comparison presupposes this: that in respect to her empirical laws nature has observed a certain economy that to our judgement appears fitting, and an understandable uniformity, and this presupposition as a principle of a priori judgement must precede all comparison." Whether 10 in the strict morphology of Eliade (or the looser works of Jung or Goodenough on symbols) this "fitting economy" is assumed. There can only be a relatively limited number of systems or archetypes, though there may be an infinite number of manifestations. Comparison, while global in scope, nevertheless remains strictly limited in procedure. One may only compare within the system or between the pattern and a particular manifestation. Comparisons within the system do not take time or history into account; comparisons between the pattern and manifestation are comparisons as to the degree of manifestation and its intelligibility and do not take historical, linear development into account. If a series is proposed, it will deal with the movement from the simple to the complex, from the perfect manifestation to the fractured--in Goethe's term, with metamorphosis (compare Eliade on degradation, infantilism, etc., in Patterns, chapter XIII). THE EVOLUTIONARY In what I have termed the second stage of development of scientific theory, the comparative anatomists introduced the temporal dimension. Buflon, Cuvier, Lamarck, and Darwin drew the implication that an increased complexity reflected a process of growth, adaptation, and evolution. In so doing, they abandoned the atemporal presuppositions of their predecessors and concentrated more and more on the variability, the internal history of individual species. One might claim that with the introduction of a temporal frame of reference, the comparative method, in the strict sense, was abandoned. As I have suggested, Comparative Religion as it was practiced in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries was essentially an illegitimate combination of the older morphological approach to comparison and the newer evolutionary frame of reference. As among the older comparative morphologists, the comparative religionists held that structures were to be studied and compared without regard to chronology and geography (or speciation, for that matter); but rather as to an increased order of complexity. However this was linked by the anthropologists and comparative religionists to an overall evolutionary frame of reference. The analyses of structure and the taxonomic classifications were employed to demonstrate a chronological chain of religious and cultural evolution on a global scale. Paradoxically (and impossibly), the newer evolutionary and temporal perspective was linked to the older ahistorical methodology. The detection of simplicity now yielded historical origins (e.g., "the primitive") rather than "logical" Urformen. The cultural evolutionists wedded this hybrid method to the encyclopaedic style of presenting data. The dynamics of this mode (as discussed above), its contextless lists, its lack of depth, its "hard" surface made this style ideal for avoiding the implications arising from this combination of methods. As was the case in the encyclopaedic style, a careful examination of the works of the cultural evolutionists will reveal no principles of organization or comparison. The meticulous arrangement of series, the micromovements and variations so essential to the biological evolutionists' work, were totally lacking in the studies of their cultural counterparts. 11 The problems inherent in this combination are displayed with 'clarity in the introduction to E. B. Tylor's classic work, Primitive Culture (1871). Tylor begins with a rather confused attempt to apply the Linnaean category of species to cultural phenomena: "What the ethnographer's task is like may be almost perfectly illustrated by comparing these details of culture with the species of plants and animals as studied by the naturalist. To the ethnographer the bow and arrow is a species, the habit of flattening children's skulls is a species, and the practice of reckoning numbers by tens is a species. The geographical distribution of these things and I their transmission from region to region, have to be studied as the (naturalist studies the geography of his botanical and zoological species." This attempt to answer the question of what in culture / corresponds to the morphologist's organism or the evolutionist's (species remains unconvincing in Tylor as well as in later theorists. As Levi-Strauss shrewdly observed, "The historical validity of the naturalist's reconstructions is guaranteed, in the final analysis, by the biological link of reproduction. An ax, on the contrary, does not generate another ax." As Tylor continued to articulate his methodological presupposition, it became clear that he was dependent upon the combination of evolution with an ahistorical methodology. The purpose of his scheme of classification is that of demonstrating "how the phenomena of culture may be classified and arranged, stage by stage, in a probable order of evolution." But in so doing Tylor claimed, as had the older comparative morphologists, the privilege of ignoring chronology and geography: "Little respect need be had in such comparisons for date in history or for place on the map; the ancient Swiss lake-dweller may be set beside the Medieval Aztec, and the Ojibwa of North America beside the Zulu of South Africa. As Dr. Johnson contemptuously said when he had read about the Patagonians and South Sea Islanders in Hawkesworth's Voyages, 'one set of savages is like another.' How true a generalization this really is, any Ethnological Museum may show." Comparison and the recognition of parallels, in such a program, might be divorced from historical studies and considerations. Similarities were to be explained on the basis of their reflecting similar "logical stages" of human development and cultural evolution (the Urmensch corollary to the Urpflanze) though, again impossibly, chronological implications were to be drawn. This hypothesis and its relationship to theories drawn from comparative anatomy was clearly formulated by J. G. Frazer in the "Preface" to the concluding part of The Golden Bough: "If there is one general conclusion which seems to emerge from this mass of particulars, I venture to think that it is the essential similarity in the working of the less developed human mind among all races, which corresponds to the essential similarity in their bodily frame revealed by comparative anatomy." These two legacies from biological theories-the linkage of the comparative method to evolutionary presuppositions and its ahistorical method-combined in a motley hybrid, when brought over into the cultural realm and religious scholarship came swiftly under attack. Perhaps the most significant critic was the doyen of American anthropology, Franz Boas, in his article first published in 1896 entitled "The Limitations of the Comparative Method of Anthropology." In this paper (which had great impact when published, even though its argument seems slight today), Boas insisted that "the same phenomena may develop in a multitude of ways" and "demanded" that "comparisons be restricted to those phenomena 12 which have been proved to be the effects of the same cause"- thus attempting to introduce an analogue of "the biological link of reproduction" (Levi-Strauss). It needs to be stressed that Boas did not reject comparison per se, as this point was immediately misunderstood by some of Boas's American and British colleagues. Indeed, as late as 1938, he called for "a cultural morphology founded on comparative studies of similar forms in different parts of the world."64 He sought rather to improve the method, to tighten up the criteria by which similarities were determined and on the basis of which comparisons might be made. He did so by introducing the temporal dimension so important to the biological researches of his time. Boas suggested the employment of what he termed "the historical method"; "Historical inquiry must be considered the critical test that science must require before admitting facts as evidence. By means of it, the comparability of the collected material must be tested, and uniformity of processes must be demanded as proof of comparability. " The results of this article were unfortunate. Boas had linked comparison to naive evolutionary theory and had juxtaposed what he termed historical method to this combination, thus setting off a conflict which continues to the present day (Boas's historical method, it may be noted, seems no less naive today). With the general loss of faith in social Darwinism and theories of progress, with the rising dominance of historicistic and positivistic thinking in the social sciences, Boas's article could be and was used as the excuse for jettisoning the comparative enterprise and for purging one's work of all but the most limited and specific comparisons. As Paul Mercier noted in his recent history of Anthropology, Boas's article represented the end of an era. The problem for History of Religions today is that a new era has not yet arrived to take its place. And thus we need to reflect on our own history, for: "If anthropology returns to the comparative method, it will certainly not forget what it has learned meanwhile in general and what it has learned about the limitations of the method in particular. It will return only in that spiral like movement, so characteristic of scientific thought, arriving after half a century at the same point but at a higher level. It will know better how and what to compare than it knew fifty years ago." This applies to our discipline as well. AFTER WORD The discussion of general methodological principles for comparison has not advanced since the original publication of this essay. See, among others, the excellent reviews of the state of the question by Gopala Sarana, The Methodology of Anthropological Comparisons: An Analysis of Comparative Methods in Social and Cultural Anthropology)' ([Viking Fund Publications in Anthropology, Number VIII Tucson, 1975) and Ulrich Weisstein, Comparative Literature and Literary Theory: Survey and Introduction (Bloomington, 1973) both of which contain rich bibliographies. Note should be taken of the careful specification of eight modes of comparison within a limited area by Morton Smith, Tannaitic Parallels to the Gospels ([Journal of Biblical Literature Monograph Series, Volume VI] Philadelphia, 1951) and its effective application by Jacob Neusner, Aphrahat and Judaism: The Christian-Jewish Argument in Fourth-Century Iran ([Studia Post-Biblica, Vol. XIX] Leiden, 1971) esp. pp. 187-195. If latitude be still 13 permitted on the ,,wider cross-cultural comparisons, surely this much ought to be required of any historian of religions working within a particular cultural context.