Baxandall, Michael The Period Eye Baxandall, Michael, (1988) "The Period Eye" from Michael Baxandall, Painting and experience in fifteenth century Italy : a primer in the social history of pictorial style pp.29-57, Oxford: Oxford University Press © Staff and students of the University of Edinburgh are reminded that copyright subsists in this extract and the work from which it was taken. This Digital Copy has been made under the terms of a CLA licence which allows you to: * access and download a copy; * print out a copy; Please note that this material is for use ONLY by students registered on the course of study as stated in the section below. All other staff and students are only entitled to browse the material and should not download and/or print out a copy. This Digital Copy and any digital or printed copy supplied to or made by you under the terms of this Licence are for use in connection with this Course of Study. You may retain such copies after the end of the course, but strictly for your own personal use. All copies (including electronic copies) shall include this Copyright Notice and shall be destroyed and/or deleted if and when required by the University of Edinburgh. Except as provided for by copyright law, no further copying, storage or distribution (including by e-mail) is permitted without the consent of the copyright holder. The author (which term includes artists and other visual creators) has moral rights in the work and neither staff nor students may cause, or permit, the distortion, mutilation or other modification of the work, or any other derogatory treatment of it, which would be prejudicial to the honour or reputation of the author. This is a digital version of copyright material made under licence from the rightsholder, and its accuracy cannot be guaranteed. Please refer to the original published edition. Licensed for use for the course: "History of Art 1". Digitisation authorised by Stuart Scarles ISBN: 019282144X n. The period eye I. AN OBJECT reflects a pattern of light on to the eye. The light enters the eye through the pupil, is gathered by the lens, and thrown on the screen at the back of the eye, the retina. On the retina is a network of nerve fibres which pass the light through a system ofcells to several millions ofreceptors, the cones. The cones are sensitive both to light and to colour, and they respond by carrying information about light and colour to the brain. It is at this point that human equipment for visual perception ceases to be uniform, from one man to the next. The brain must interpret the raw data about light and colour that it receives from the cones and it does this with innate skills and those developed out of experience. It tries out relevant items from its stock of patterns, categories, habits of inference and analogy'round', 'grey', 'smooth', 'pebble' would be verbalized examples -and these lend the fantastically complex ocular data a structure and therefore a meaning. This is done at the cost of a certain simplification and distortion: the relative aptness of the category 'round' overlays a more complex reality. But each of us has had different experience, and so each of us has slightly different . knowledge and skills of interpretation. Everyone, in fact, processes the data from the eye with different equipment. In practice these differences are quite small, since most experience is common to us all: we all recognize our own species and its limbs, judge distance and elevation, infer and assess movement, and many other things. Yet in some circumstances the otherwise marginal differences between one man and another can take on a curious prominence. Suppose a man is shown the configuration in plate 13, a configuration that can be apprehended in various ways. One way would be primarily as a round thing with a pair' ofelongated L-shaped projections on each side. Another way would be primarily as a circular form superimposed on a broken rectangular form. There are many other ways of perceiving it as well. That which we tend toward will depend on many thingsparticularly on the context of the configuration, which is suppressed here for the moment-but not least on the interpreting 29 29 • '3. Santo Brasca. ItinerariIJ . di Gerusalemme (Milan, '4.8,)· p. 58 v. \Voorlcu L skills one happens to possess, the categories, the model patterns and the habits of inferefIce and analogy; in short, what we may call one's COl;nitive style. Suppose the man looking at plate 13 is well equipped with patterns and concepts of shape like those in plate 14 and is practised in using them. (In fact, most of the people plate 13 was originally made for were proud of being so equipped.) This man will be disposed to the second of the ways of perceiving the configuration. He will be less likely to see it just as a round thing with projections, and more likely to see it primarily as a circle superimposed on a rectangle: he possess'es these categories and is practised at distinguishing such patterns in complicated shapes. To this extent he will see plate 13 differently from a man without resources of this kind. Let us now add a context to plate 13. It occurs in a description of the Holy Land printed in Milan in 1481 and it has the caption: 'Questo e la forma del sancto sepulchro de meser iesu christo.' (This is the shape of the Holy Sepulchre of Our Lord Jesus Christ). The context adds two particularly important factors to the perception of the configuration. First, one now knows that it has been made with the purpose of representing something: the man looking at it refers to his experience of representational conventions and is likely to decide that it belongs to the groundplan convention-lines representing the course walls would follow on the ground if one were looking vertically down at a structure. The groundplan is a relatively abstract and analytical convention for representing things, and unless it is within his culture-as it is within ours-the man may be puzzled as to how to interpret the figure. Second, one has been cued to the fact that prior 30 .... 't-oo I r'Ificb_·1 _~111 , Q'\/ ;~L\LS:~" - --""'" ~BE7 14. Euclid. Elementa .eeometTlae (Venice, 1482). p. 2 r. Woodcut. experience of buildings is relevant here, and one will make inferences accordingly. A man used to fifteenth-century Italian architecture might well in!er .that the circle is a circular building, with a cupola perhaps, and that the rectangular wings are halls. But a fifteenth-century Chinese, once he had learned the groundplan convention, might infer a circular central court on the lines of the new Temple of Heaven at Peking. So here are three variable and indeed culturally relative kinds of thing the mind brings to interpreting the pattern of light 31 15. Bartolo da Sassoferra!o. DejlllminibuJ (Rome, [483). p. 18 r. Woodcut. plate 13 casts on the retina: a stock of patterns, categories and methods of inference; training in a range of representational conventions; and experience, drawn from the environment, in what are plausible ways of visualizing what we have incomplete information about. In practice they do not work serially, as they are described here, but together; the process is indescribably complex and still obscure in its physiological detail. 2. All this may seem very distant from the way we look at a picture, but it is not. Plate 15 is the representation of a river and at least two distinct representational conventions are being used in it. The mermaids and the miniature landscape on the left are represented by lines indicating the contours of forms, and the point of view is from a slightly upward angle. The course of the river and the dynamics of its flow are registered diagrammatically and geometrically, and the point of view is from vertically above. A linear ripple convention on the water surface mediates between one style of representation and the other. The first convention is more immediately related to what we see, where the second is more abstract and conceptualized-and to us now rather unfamiliar-but they both involve a skill and a willingness to interpret marks on paper as representations simpHfying an aspect of reality within accepted rules: we do not see a tree as a white plane surface circumscribed by black lines. Yet the tree is only a crude version of what one has in a picture, and the variable pressures on perception, the cognitive style, also operate on anyone's perception of a painting. We will take Piero della Francesca's Annunciation fresco at 32 Arezzo (Colour Plate I) as an example. In the first place, understanding the picture depends on acknowledging a representational convention, of which the central part is that a man is pigments on a two-dimensional ground in order to something that is three-dimensional: one must enter into of the game, which is not the groundplan game but someBoccaccio described very well: The painter exerts himself to make any figure he paints-actually a) little colour applied with skill to a panel-similar in its action to a figure which is the product of Nature and naturally has that action: so that it can deceive the eyes of the beholder, either partly or completely, making itself be taken for what it really is not. In fact, since our vision is stereoscopic, one is not normally long deceived by such a picture to the point of completely supposing it real. Leonardo da Vinci pointed this out: It is not possible for a painting, even if it is done with the greatest perfection of outline, shadow, light and colour, to appear in the same relief as the natural model, unless that natural model were looked at from a great distance and with only one eye. He adds a drawing (plate 16) to demonstrate why this is so: A and B are our eyes, C the object seen, E-F behind it, D-G the area screened by a painted object, but real life seen. But the convention was that the painter made his flat surface very suggestive of a three-dimensional world and was credit for doing so. Looking at such representations was a fifteenth-century Italian institution, and involved in the institution were certain expectations; these varied according to the 16. After Leonardo da Vinci. Stereoscopic vision. From I.ibm di pittura, Vatican Library, MS. Urb. lat. 1270, rol. 155 v. E 33 placing of the picture--church or salone- but one expectation \\ as constant: the beholder expected skill, as we have seen, Quite \\ hat sort of ~kill he expectt·d will OCCUPy llS presently, but the poim to be noticed no\\' is that a fifteenth-cemury man looking at a picture was curiously on his mettle. He was aware that the good picture embodied skill and he was frequently assured that it was the part of the culti\'ated behokkr to make discrimillationabout thaI skill, and sometimes even to do so verball) . T he most popular fifteenth-century treatJ~e on education, for example, Pier Paolo Vergerio\ 011 71obl, IJthalllllur of q04. reminded him : 'The beaut) and grace of objects, both natural ones and those made by man's art, are thing5 it is proper for men of distinction to be able to discllss with each other and appreciate.' Looking at Piero's paiming, a man witlt intellectual self-respect was in no posi tion to remain quite passive; he was obliged to discriminate. This brings us to the second point, which is that the picturc is sensitive to the kinds of interpretative ski 11- pallerns, categories, inferences, ana logies the mind 13rings to it. A man's capacity to distinguish a certain kind of form or relationship of forms will have consequences for the allen tion with which he addresses a picture. For instance. ir he is skilled in noting proponional relationships. or if he is practiced in reducing complex forms to compounds of simple forms, or if he has a rich set of categories for different kinds of red and brown, these skills may well lead him to order his experience of Piero delJa Francesca;s Annunciation differently from people without these skills. and much more sharply than people whose experience has not gi\"en them many skills relevant to the picturt'. For it is clear that some percept ual skills are more relevant to anyone picture than others: a virtuosity in classifying the ductus of flexing lines-a skill many Germans, for instance, possessed in this period-or a functional knowledge of the surface musculature of the human body would not find much scope on the Annullciation. Much of" what we call 'taste' lies in this, the conformity between discriminations demanded by a painting and skills of discrimination possessed by the beholdl'r. We enjoy our own exercise of skill, and we particularly enjoy the playful exercise of skills which we use in normal life very earnestly. If a painting gives us opportunity for exercising a valued skill and rewards our virtuosity with a sense of worthwhile insights about that paintin!;'s organization, \'\; e tend 10 enjoy it : it is to our taste::, The negative of this is the man without the sorts of skill in terms of which the painting is ordered : a German calligrapher ronfronted by a Piero della Francesca, perhaps. 3 ·~ Thirdly again . one brir~ tro the picturt' a mass of information and assumptions drawn I'\.n general cxpc·rit·nce. Our uwn culture is close enou~h to th&.uatt roccnw fill' llS to take a lot o/" the ~ame things for granted .J not to have a strong sense uf misunderstanding the pictum: we are doser to the Quattroccllto mind than to the B\'Za r;J~e, for instance. This can make it difficult to realize ho~ m h of our comprehension depends on what we bring to the picI1W(" To take two contrasting kinds of such kno\\ It'dgt', if one c, lei remove from one's perception of Piero della Francesca's .+,mciatioll both (a) the aswmption that the building units arc likr to be rectangular and regular, and (b) knowledge of the Anrnciation story, one would have difficulty in maklllg it out. f . the first, in spite of Piero's rigorous perspective construction-:tstlf a mode of representation the fifteenth-century Chmesc ould have had problems with- the logic of the picturt, depcr" heavily on our assumption thal the loggia project~ al a right J,~le from the nack walJ: suppress this assumption and one i ~ thrvn into uncertainty about thr whole spatial layou t of the seen.. Perhaps the loggia is shallower than onc thought, its ceiling ~:'pinl:{ down backwards and its corner thrusting out toward~ thf rft in an acute angle, then the tiles of the pavement will be 102'i;):(es. not oblongs . . . and so on. A clearer case : remove lh assumption of ff'gularit) and rectangularit~ from the lor~xj 3;rchitecture of Domenico Vencl.iano'~ .1nnU/uil1litll' {plate 17. li)~e to tak\> Ii}f granlcc1 l'ither that the 17. n UIJIIlli.." \ ·" llI"/i,IIII'. '1/11 .~ullljali"" ,IlJuul 1+-1 .'/ . C"mbrid"r, ("ill" illiilllI "tuM'lIm. Pa nd o walls of the courtyard meet at right angles or that the foreshortened rows of columns are spaced at the same intervals as the row seen face on-and the picture space abruptly telescopes into a shallow little area. Regarding knowledge of the story, if one did not know about the Annunciation it would be difficult to know quite what was happening in Piero's painting; as a critic once pointed out, if all Christian knowledge were lost, a person could well suppose that both figures, the Angel Gabriel and Mary, were directing some sort of devout attention to the column. This does not mean that Piero was telling his story badly; it means he could depend on the beholder to recognize the Annunciation subject promptly enough for him to accent, vary and adjust it in rather advanced ways. In this case, Mary's stance frontal to us serves various purposes: first, it is a device Piero uses to induce participation the beholder; second, it counters on this occasion the fact that its position in the chapel at Arezzo causes the beholder to see the fresco rather from the right; third, it helps to register a particular moment in Mary'S story, a moment of reserve towards the Angel previous to her final submission to her destiny. For fifteenthcentury people differentiated more sharply than us between successive stages of the Annunciation, and the sort of nuance we now miss in Quattrocento representations of the Annunciation is one of the things that will have to engage us later. 3- Renaissance people were, as has been said, on their mettle before a picture, because of an expectation that cultivated people should be able to make discriminations about the interest of pictures. These very often took the form of a preoccupation with the painter's skill, and we h,ave seen too that this preoccupation was something firmly anchored in certain economic and intellectual conventions and assumptions. But the only practical way of publicly making discriminations is verbally: the Renaissance beholder was a man under some pressure to have words that fitted the interest of the object. The occasion might be one when actual enunciation of words was appropriate, or it might be one when internal possession of suitable categories assured him of his own competence in relation to the picture. In any event, at some fairly high level of consciousness the Renaissance man was one who matched concepts with pictorial style. This is one of the things that makes the kind of culturally relative pressures on perception we have been discussing so very important for Renaissance perception of pictures. In our own 36 culture there is a class of over-cultivated person who, though he is not a painter himself, has learned quite an extensive range of specialized categories of pictorial interest, a set of words and concepts specific to the quality of paintings: he can talk of 'tactile values', or of 'diversified images'. In the fifteenth century there were some such people, but they had relatively few special concepts, if only because there was then such a small literature of art. Most of the people the painter catered for had half-adozen or so such categories for the quality of pictures-'foreshortening', 'ultramarine at two florins an ounce', 'drapery' perhaps, and a few others we shall be meeting-and then were thrown back on their more general resources. Like most of us now, his real training in consciously precise and complex visual assessment of objects, 'both natural ones and those made by man's art', was not on paintings but on things more immediate to his well-being and social survival: The beauty of the horse is to be recognized above all in its having a body so broad and long that its members correspond in a regular fashion with its breadth and length (plates 18-19). The head of the horse should be proportionately slender, thin and long. The mouth wide and cut; the nostrils broad and distended. The eyes should not be hollowed nor deeply recessed; the ears should be small and carried like spears; the neck long and rather slender towards the head, the jaw quite slender and thin, the mane sparse and straight. The chest should be broad and fairly round, the thighs not tapering but rather straight and even, the croup short and quite flat, the loins round and rather thick,-the ribs and other like parts also thick, the haunches long and even, the crupper long and wide.... The horse should be taller before than behind, to the same degree a deer is, and should carry its head high, and the thickness of its neck should be proportionable with its chest. Anyone who wants to be a judge of horses' beauty must consider all the parts of the horse discussed above as parts related in proportion to the height and breadth of the horse.... But there is a distinction to be made between the general run of visual skills and a preferred class of skills specially relevant to the perception of works of art. The skills weare most aware of are not the ones we have absorbed like everyone else in infancy, but those we have learned formally, with conscious effort: those which we have been taught. And here in turn there is a correlation with skills that can be talked about. Taught skills commonly have rules and categories, a terminology and stated standards, which are the medium through which they are teachable. These two things-the confidence in a relatively advanced 37 works of an \\ as Impor lant to till' arti~t-tlw patronizing- classes, one migh t ~ay. 1n effect this means ra ther a \mall pr()poT\IOn or the population : mercantile and profeSSIOnal mrn, aClil1~ as :~8 ,. 141 "-~. ~-'r 39 members of (onfralernilie~ or as individuab, princes and their courtiers. the senior memhers of religious houses. The peasants and the urban poor playa very small part in the Renaissance culture that most interem u~ now, which rna) be deplorable hut is a faCl lhat must be accepted . Yet among the patronizing lasses there were variations, not just the inevitable va riation from maIl to man, but variation hy groups. So a certain proicssion, for instance, lead~ a man to discriminate particularly efficiently in identifiable areas. Fifteenth-cemury medicine trained a physician to obsrrve the relations of member to member or the human body as a means to diagnosis, and a doctor was alert and equipped to notice mallers of proportion in painting too. But while it is clear that among the painter's public Ihere were many 19. Aft"1 Lenllard" d" "inri. Dillu·IHi.m, .if Il /lOr." . :\,.\\ y".~, I'ic·rpuli. ~1".~"11 Lilm"l. 1\1'>. :\1.,\.. 1.39. fui. /l~ r. 1" '11 .lIltl ,1l..lIk. tv>tt'~ fl,II<1" 1 "' I. - -" - °l't ;3 r' f - ­ -1­ ~~ t C - ­ .J-' , 6 ,. r' j t--.c-tor..--­ J. 6' to - _ _ -L_": . ,H ~ Ilo - • . -/ - 1 I r. lJ' t' 19­ - - -.J 18. I'isanrllo. ~/lu"r.\ '1n 1/111." Cnd.' al lardi ·J,lfi8 .. l'ilris. 1 ' >I]\'It·, 1" '11 ;'11<1 ,.f\,dk . and \alued skill, and the availabil ity of'verbal reSOurces associa led with them- make such skiIJs particularh su~n'plible tn transfer in situaLiom \uch al> that of a man in front of a pillUre. This raises a problem. We have been moving towards a notion of a Quallrocento c;ognilive st) Ie. By th is one would mean th equipment that the fIftecnlh-centUl) painter's public bruught tn complex visual stimulations like pictures. One IS talking not almul ali Iiflcenth -cen tury people, bu t a bou t I hose whose respons(' I subgroups with special visual skills and habits-the painters themselves were one such subgroup--this book will be concerned with more generally accessible styles of discrimination. A Quattrocento man handled affairs, went to church, led a social life; from all of these activities he acquired skills relevant to his observation of painting. It is true that one man would be stronger on business skills, another on pious skills, another on polite skills; but every man had something of each of these, whatever the individual balance, and it is the highest common factor of skill in his public that the painter consistently catered for. To sum up: some of the mental equipment a man orders his visual experience with is variable, and much of this variable equipment is culturally relative, in the sense of being determined by the society which has influenced his experience. Among these variables are categories with which he classifies his visual stimuli, the knowledge he will use to supplement what his immediate vision gives him, and the attitude he will adopt to the kind of artificial object seen. The beholder must use on the painting such visual skills as he has, very few of which are normally special to painting, and he is likely to use those skills his society esteems highly. The painter responds to this; his public's visual capacity must be his medium. Whatever his own specialized professional skills, he is himself a member of the society he works for and shares its visual experience and habit. We are concerned here with Quattrocento cognitive style as it relates to Quattrocento pictorial style. This chapter must now exemplify the kinds of visual skill a Quattrocento person was distinctively equipped with, and try to show how these were relevant to painting. 4. Most fifteenth-century pictures are religious pictures. This is self-evident, in one sense, but 'religious pictures' refers to more than just a certain range of subject matter; it means that the pictures existed to meet institutional ends, to help with specific intellectual and spiritual activities. It also means that the pictures came within the jurisdiction of a mature body of ecclesiastical theory about images. There is no sign of the more academic elaborations of this theory being active in many people's minds during the fifteenth century, though they were quite often rehearsed by the theologians, but a few of the basic principles still set standards for the pictures much more real for the public mind than some of the artistic theory we make so much of now. What was the religious function of religious pictures? In the 40 Church's view the purpose of images was threefold. John of Genoa's late thirteenth-century Catholicon, still a standard dictionary of the period, summarized them in this way: Know that there were three reasons for the institution of images in churches. First, for the instruction of simple people, because they are instructed by them as if by books. Second, so that the mystery of the incarnation and the examples of the Saints may be the more active in our memory through being presented daily to our eyes. Third, to excite feelings of devotion, these being aroused more effectively by things seen than by things heard. In a sermon published in '492 the Dominican Fra Michele da Carcano gives an orthodox Quattrocento expansion of this: ... images of the Virgin and the Saints were introduced for three reasons. First, on account of the ignorance of simple people, so that those who are not able to read the scriptures can yet learn by seeing the sacraments of our salvation and faith in pictures. It is written; 'I have learned that, inflamed by unconsidered zeal, you have been destroying the images of the saints on the grounds that they should not be adored. And we praise you wholeheartedly for not allowing them to be adored, but we blame you for breaking them ... For it is one thing to adore a painting, but it is quite another to learn from a painted narrative what to adore. What a book is to those who can read, a picture is to the ignorant ·f people who look at it. Because in a picture even the unlearned may i see what example they should follow; in a picture they who know no letters may yet read.' St. Gregory the Great wrote these words to Serenus, Bishop of Marseilles. Second, images were introduced on account of our emotional sluggishness; so that men who are not aroused to devotion when they hear about the histories of the Saints may at least be moved when they see them, as if actually present, in pictures. For our feelings are aroused by things seen more than by things heard. Third, they were introduced on account of our unreliable memories .... Images were introduced because many people cannot retain in their memories what they hear, but they do remember if they see images. If you commute these three reasons for images into instructions for the beholder, it amounts to using pictures as respectively lucid, vivid and readily accessible stimuli to meditation on the Bible and the lives of Saints. If you convert them into a brief for the painter, they carry an expectation that the picture should tell its story in a clear way for the simple and in an eye-catching and memorable way for the forgetful, and with full use of all the emotional resources of the sense of sight, the most powerful as well as the most precise of the senses. Of course, the matter could not always be as simple and as 4' rational as this; there were abuses both in people's responses to pictures and in the way the pictures themselves were made. Idolatry was a standing preoccupation of theology: it was fully realized that simple people could easily confuse the image of divinity or sanctity with divinity or sanctity itself, and worship it. There were widely reported phenomena that tended to go with irrational responses to the images; a story in Sicco Polentone's Life of St. Anthony of Padua printed in 1476: Pope Boniface VIII ... had the old and ruinous Basilica of St. John Lateran at Rome rebuilt and redecorated with much care and expense, and he listed by name which saints were to be depicted in it. The painters of the Order of Minor Friars were preeminent in this art and there were two particularly good masters from this Order. When these two had painted up all the saints the Pope had ordered, on their own initiative they added in a blank space pictures of Sts. Francis and When the Pope heard about this he was angered by their disrespect of his orders. 'I can tolerate the St. Francis,' he said, 'as it is now done. But I insist on the St. Anthony being removed completely.' However all the people sent by the Pope to carry out this command were thrown down to the ground, fiercely knocked about and driven away by a terrible, resounding, gigantic spirit. When the Pope heard of this, he said: 'Let the St. Anthony alone, then, since we can see he wants to stay; in conflict with him, we can only lose more than we ' But idolatry never became as publicly scandalous and pressing a problem as it did in Germany; it was an abuse on which theologians regularly discoursed, but in a stereotyped and rather unhelpful way. Lay opinion usually felt able to dismiss it as an abuse of pictures that did not constitute a condemnation of the institution of images itself; as the humanist Chancellor of Florence Coluccio Salutati had described it: 1 think [an ancient Roman's] leelings about their religious images were no different from what we in the full rectitude ofour faith feel now about the painted or carved memorials of our Saints and Martyrs. For we perceive these not as Saints and as Gods but rather as images of God and the Saints. It may indeed be that the ignorant vulgar think more and otherwise of them than they should. But one enters into understanding and knowledge of spiritual things through the medium of sensible things, and so if pagan people made images of Fortune with a cornucopia and a rudder~as distributing wealth and controlling human affairs~they did not deviate very much from the truth. So too, when our own artist~ represent Fortune as a queen turning with her hands a revolving wheel, so long as we apprehend that picture as made by a man's hand, not something itself divine but a similitude divine providence, direction and order~and representing indeed not 42 its essential character but rather the winding and turning of mundane affairs who can reasonably complain? The abuse was agreed to exist in some measure but did not stimulate churchmen to new thoughts or action on the problem. As for the pictures themselves, the Church realized there were sometimes faults against theology and good taste in their conception. S. Antonino, Archbishop of Florence, sums up the three main errors: Painters are to be blamed when they paint things contrary to our Faith--when they represent the Trinity as one person with three heads, a monster; or, in the Annunciation, an already formed infant, Jesus, being sent into the Virgin's womb, as if the body he took on were not of her substance; or when they paint the infant Jesus with a hornbook, even though he never learned from man. But they are not to be praised either when they paint apocryphal matter, like midwives at the Nativity, or the Virgin Mary in her Assumption handing down her girdle to St. Thomas on account of his doubt (plate :20), and so on. Also, to curiosities into the stories of Saints and in churches, things that do not, serve to arouse devotion but laughter and vain thoughts~monkeys, and dogs chasing hares and so on, or gratuitously elaborate costumes--­ this I think unnecessary and vain. Subjects with heretical implications, apocryphal subjects, subjects obsc»red by a f!ivolous and indecorous treatment. Again, all three of these faults did exist. Christ was erroneously shown learning to read in many paintings. The apocryphal story of St. Thomas and the Virgin's girdle was the largest sculptured decoration on S. Antonino's own cathedral church at Florence, the Porta della Mandorla, and appears in numerous paintings. Gentile da Fabriano's Adoration oftke Magi (plate 21), painted for the Florentine merchant and humanist Palla Strozzi in 1423, has the monkeys, dogs and elaborate costumes S. Antonino considered unnecessary and vain. But, also again, the complaint is not new or particularly of its time; it is just a Q!.Iattrocento version of a stock theologian's complaint, voiced continually from St. Bernard to the Council of Trent. When S. Antonino looked at the painting of his time he might well have felt that, on the whole, the Church's three functions for painting were fulfilled: that most pictures were (I) clear, (2) attractive and memorable, (3) stirring registrations of the holy stories. If he had not, he was certainly the man to so. So the first question-What was religious function of religious paintings ?----can be reformulated, or at least replaced a new question: What sort of painting would the religious 43 ' / ' (. ·l· , 'D. ..lIlile d.. Fabnann. 7/" :ldnrali'l/I oj lit, .\Ia~i ( 1.j2'l:. I-ll1rrnn", l fllzi . I'and. public for picturcs have found lucid, vi\idly memorable, and emotionally moving? 5. The painter was a professional visualizer of the holy stories. What we now easily Jorget is that each of his pious public was liable lO be an amateur in the same line, practised in spiritual exercises that demanded a high level of visualization of, at lcast. the central episodes of the lives of Christ and Mary. To adapt a theological distinction, tht' painter's \H:re exterior visualizations, the public's interior Visualizations. The public mind \\ d~ not a blank tablet on which the painters' representations of a story or person could impress themselves; it was an active institution of interior visualization with v. hich en' l) paintt'l" had LO grt along. In this respect thc fiftecnth-cct1luJ"\ experience of a painting was not the painting wesel? now so much as a marria~e between the painting' and the heholder's previous visualizing acti\'itv on the same matter. .J.5 So it is important lx'!ore all cl~c 10 know roughly wllat son of ani\itv this was. One handbook that is lIsdulJy explicit is the ,:;'mdillo d, OT(l//fm, tIlt' (,(Irdl'n fir Pray,.. written for )'fJung girls in J..jj.j and Idler printcd ill Vt"lliLl . The book explains the need for inlt'rnal repn'scnt..ttirJlls and their placl' in the process of prayer: The heller to impre" the "IOl). 01' the I'as,ioll on \,/)Ul mind. and to mr-mc.risl' each at linn or il mon° l'a~ily, it is 1\t'lrful and 11l'CeSSan 10 fix the places and people in your mmd : a city. hH example, \, hieh will be the cilY ()r.Jc>ru~altm laking 1(lr thi~ purpmc ,I rit)' that is \\ell known to VOli . In Ihis cit} find the prillf'ipal pic-Ices in \,hi! h alllhc ('pisode~ of Iht Passion woulci hu\e laken place IiII' install!"" , a palace with till' supper-room \,I1('rc Chri,I had the LJ.sI "uppc'r "\th the DIsciples. and the house of Anne, and that of Caiaphas, ,\i ' h til!' "Iact \\ hc're J esus was taken in the night, and th(' mom \\ here He wa~ brouf5ht belore Caiaphas and mocked and beal("n. \Iso th!' rl'~itlc-ntc "f Pilate wlll'rt· he spoke with the Jews. and in itthe room wherc.Jesus W ' I' I)(.und to the Column. Abo the si te of ~1ount Calvary, ",here he was put on the Cross; and other like places. And then 100 you must shape in vour mmd som,' people, peopl(~ w("l1known to you. tl) reprrst'nt for you th(' people \lIVO" c·d in the Passiontlte peP.ion of J(,S\l~ Himself. of the \ 'irgin, ~ai"t P,'IIT, Saim John the Evangelist, Saim Mary ~Iagdalen, Anne, Caiaphas, IJllatc. .Juda~ and lhe ot lu:rs, everyone or whonl ) ou will fashion in your mmd . \"'hen you have done all titts, pUlling all ,our imagination illu, it, Ihen go into your chamber. ....Ione and solitary. excludint( C\Trv external thought from your mind, start thinl.ing of. the bt'ginnin~ or till: Passion, starling with how Jesus entered Jerusalem 011 tlte ass. MO\'ing slowlv from episodt' to cpisode, m,'ditate 011 eat:h onc, dwelling on each single stage and step of tht slOry. And if at any roil'll you feci a sensation or piety, stop : do not pas~ on as long as that s\\eCI and devout sen timen t lasts. .. This sort of experience, a visualizing meditation on the storie~ particularized to the point of perhaps ~eltil1l{ them in onc's own city and casting them from one's own acquaintallce, is somcthinf{ most of us now lack. It gav/" the painter'S exterior visualizations a curious function. The painter could not compete with Iht particularity of the privatt: representation, When beholder<: might approach his painting with preconcci\'ed interior pictures of such detail, each person's di fTerem, L1w painter did not al> a rule try to give detailed characteriza tions of people and places: it would have been an inter/erenre with the indi\ idual's priv3lt, \ iSlIalilation if he had . Painters specially popular in pious circles, like Perugino (piau· 22). painted peopl! \\ It" an' !(,cllt'ral. IlI1particlIlariz!'o, int!'r­ {G N. l'rrul.,'illo. I tllI/mllllioll (11(/ Iii, I)",d (.'/11111 1.f95 1'1011'11' t . l'ilIM~(J l'illi . 1',111..1. hangcablc types. They provided a bast' firmly concrete and very evocative in it!. patterns of people-on \\ hicIJ the piou5 beholder could impose hi~ personal detail, more particular but less strurtured than what the painter offered . It was not only a painter like Perugino that worked within conditions of this kind, though IllS respome to them was much appreciated. A great dcal of the quality of the most central rxperiences of Quattrocento painting -let us say, of ~'1asa('cio's Tribute A/mu:..l' (platt' 65 )or Bellini's Transfiguratioll (Cultlur Platt' TT' dcrives from the same situation, Bellint does not offer tlw detail I)r persons and p!acf'~ the public provided fi'lr itself'. Ht' comIlll'menb till ' hrhold('r', interior \ isioll. Hi, )Jt'NHlS and places 'f7 are generalized and yet massively concrete, and they are marshalled in patterns of strong narrative suggestion. Neither of these qualities, the concrete and the patterned, are what the beholder provided for himself since you cannot provide these qualities in mental images, as a little introspection shows; neither could come fully into play before the physical sense of sight was actually resorted to. The painting is the relic of a cooperation between Bellini and his public. the fifteenth-century experlience of the Transfiguration was an interaction between the painting, the configuration on the wall, and the visualizing activity of the public mind--a public mind with different furniture and dispositions from ours. We enjoy the Transfiguration, the painter's part in all this, because we are stimulated by its imbalance, its hype!:trophy of the weightily concrete and eloquently patterned at the permissible expense of the particular, which Bellini could count on being contributed by the other side. We should only deceive ourselves if we thought we can have the experience of the Transfiguration Bellini designed, or that it expresses in any simple way a spirit or a state of mind. The best paintings often express their culture not just directly but complementarily, because it is by complementing it that they are best designed to serve public needs: the public does not need what it has already got. What the Zardino de Oration describes are private exercises in imaginative intensity and sharpness. The painter was addressing people who were publicly exercised in the same matter too, and in more formal and analytical ways. The best guide we now have to the public exercises is the sermon. Sermons were a very important part of the painter's circumstances: preacher and picture were both part of the apparatus of a church, and each took notice of the other. The fifteenth century was the last fling of the medieval type of popular preacher: the fifth Lateran Council of 1512-17 took measures to suppress them. It is one of the underlying cultural differences between the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries in Italy. The popular preachers were no doubt tasteless and inflammatory sometimes, but they filled their teaching function irreplaceably; certainly they drilled their congregations . in a set of interpretative skills right at the centre of the fifteenthcentury response to paintings. Fra Roberto Caracciolo da Lecce . (plate 23) is a convenient example: Cosimo de' Medici thought he dressed too sharply for a priest, and his sense of the dramatic was strong-re are argu ments for either), but certainly at the season when rhe earth is co\'ering itself with grasses and flower; after the winter ; (e) Place )lazareth, meaning 'Flower', pointing to the symbolic relation or flowers to :Ylary, For the Angelic Salutalion Fra Roberto is much briefer: the Salutation implies I,al honour, the Angel kneeling to Mary, lb l exemption from the pain~ of childbinh, (e) the giving of grate, (d) union \\ith God, and (e) the unique bca Iitude of i\IaJ'), both Virgin and Mother. .°: 1"': So liu what Fra Rnberto Il a~ saicJ is mainly preliminal) or mMginal to the painter's visual drama of Mary, It iii tht: third nWl'lel)', the Angelic Colloquy, tllat throws clear light on the lir~een th-cenlurv teelin.!! lor whal, on the level of human emolion, Ilappened lu her in the crisis the painter had 10 repre~ent. Fra Roberto analyses the account (Jf St, Luke (J : :;!G 38) and lays oul a series of five succe~i \.e spiritual anti mental conditions or ~taLes attributable to Mal) : TIll third mvster') of the Annullcia tioll i~ called Angelic Colloquy: it l'omprises five Laudable Conditions of the Bles~ed Virgin: I, ClinlurlitJ.tio Disquirl 2, Cogilatio Reflection 3, II/lerro,galil, 1tlquiry 4, Humillatin Submissiun 5, J/mtalw ~Jent he first laudable CClndition is cal It'd Cllnlurvali'l; as S1. Luke wrilt:S, \\'hl"n u]e Vir~in heard the Angel's salutation 'Hail, Ih"u uri high(l' jal'oured, lilt Lnrd is wilh l/zu ,' "'(,\.I,d IlTI Illou among w/Jmen' Jhe was tToub/,d, Thi ~ disq uiet, as :\icholas of Lyra wril('S, came nnt fro m incredulit y b ut from wonder, since she was uscd to seeing anll,'eLs and marvelled not at th( fat! "f the Angel's apparition so m uch as at the lofty and gran d salutation, in "hicli the Angel lnadt: plain for her such great ancl mar\('Ilous things, and at whic-h sill' in her humility was astonished a nd .llnazed (pia l" 24 (a) , H er second laudable condlliolJ is calJed CO,gilatio: she (0.11 ill her mind hal mallna (iflll/ulali,m Ihil i/wuld he, This shows the prudence of the most Hoh' \ 'irgin, So then lilt angtl said 111110 IIrr, P,ar nol, .\I(/~.' ,' jar Iholl hasl jOllnd jarour wltll God, :Jlld, be/wId, Illou shalt (Ollceiu in III)' U'fJmb, (lIld bring 1MIII II SOTl, and sllall (all his /ltJm, JE~'l 'r;; , , . (plale 24( b,l, ' The' Ihird la uda ble condition is called IlIlarogatio, Then said MlIIy UIII Ih, IIlIgel, f/nu' ;lItJl/ tllu bt, uein,g I knQw nol a man? that is 10 sar, ' , , 'seeing f ha\t the firm rcsol v~, impin'd IJY God and confirmed by my own will, never to know a man?' Francis l\.1ayron sav~ of this: 'One w uld say the glo! iou~ Vir~ill JI;.~irt:d to be a virgin mor~ than TO conceive the Son of G0d wilhout vir~ini t y, si nce virgiuit) i~ laud'IMCI). I'll'" II. lifling her eves lO hl"aVt'lI, and bringing up her hand~ with her arms in the form of a cross, she ended a.~ God, tIlt' Angel~, and the Holv Fathers tle~ir{'d : Bf il unlO me Qaordm.e. 10 111l' Icord iplatt' 21-ld l The fifth laudable lundition is called .\Jeri/alio ' . . When she had said tlWSl' words, the An~e1 departed from her. And Lht bounleou, \ 'irl{in at once had Christ, God incarnatt", in her womb, according wilh thaI wonderful condition I spoke 01 ill my ninth sermon. So wr can Justly suppose that in the mom~nl when the Virgin \1ary conceived Christ her ~oul rose to SULh lofty alld ~ublim" contemplation of the action an swnlnes~ of divine things that. in thl' preSel1Cf: of Ihe beatific visioll, sIll passed hc:>ond tf1l' c:xperic:nl( of l \eT-y other created heillg. And th!' bodily 'ensations of the Child being prest'lll in her womb rose again with Indescribable s\\eetness. Probably, in her profound humilit) , she: raised her ey<,s to ht'a\'clI and then lowered them towards her womb \\ ilh many tears, saying something like ' ' Who am I, thaI haY(' conceived God incarnate etc. ' The imaginary monologue continues and brings Fra Rob('rto'~ sermon to its climax. The last of the five Laudable Conditions, .\lerilatio, followed after the departure of Gabriel and helongs with representations f the Vir",rin on her own, the type now caJled Aflnunziata (plate 50); lht' other four- succcssi\'Cly Disquiet, Reflection, Inquiry and Submission- were divisions within the 'iublime narrativt' of Mary's response to the Annunciation that wry exactly fit lhe painled representalions. Mosl fifteenth-ccn I ur)' An nuncia tions arc idenlifiably Annunciations ofDisquiet, or of Submission, orthese being less clearly distinguished from each other of Reflection and/or Inquiry . The preachers coached the public in tbe pdinters' reperlory. Clnd the painlers responded within the current emotional categorizaLioll 0(' the event. And though v\e, IHlprompted by Fra Roberto, respond to a general st'nsc of excitcmt'n! or thou~htfl1lness or humility in a picture or the scene, the more explicit categories of the fifteenth Ccnlur} can sharpen our perception of differences. ll1e~ remind us, ror instance, that Fra Angt'lieo in his many Annunciations never really brt'aks away from the type or Humiliafio, while Botticelli (plate 25 ) has a dangeroll\ amnit) with CUfltUlbafi(); that a number of marvellous fourteenth-century ways of registering Cogifalio and inlerrogalio become blurred and dcr3y in the fifteenth cenrury, in spite or occasional re"ival by a painter like Piero della Franc('sea; or that around 1500 painters were experimenting partieula rlY \\ ith mor!' complex and restrained types of Contl/rha!;o than that of the tradition used by BotLicelli; they shared Leonardo's dista~ tt' for the violent mode : 55 -- ~5 · IInlliu'lli TIl( .I""unria/itlll (a hnut 1+<),') . rturl"IH <". l.'lTi/i. Pall..J. some days ago I sal\ the picture of an angel who, in making the Annunciation. seemed to be trying lU chasr t-.lary OUI of hcr room, with mOVl'mcnlS showing- the sort of attack one migl't make rill \ome hated enemy; and \1ary, as if desperate. seemed to h... tryinf(" to throw herself out of the window. Do not fall int(, f'rrors like rht'" Fiftcenth-ccntun pictorial rlc\'dopmf'1l1 happened within fiftt'enth-centun dasscs of emotional experience. 6. Thr effective unit of the ~tories was the human figure . The figure's indi, idual character depended less on its physio~nomya private maller largel~ left for the beholder LO supply, as we have seen-than on the way it moved . But therr wt're exceptions to this. and particular!> the figure of Christ. The figure of Christ wa~ less open to the personal imagination than others because the fifteenth century was ~till lucky enough 56 to think it had an eye-witness account of his appearancf'. It wa~ in a forged report from a fictitious Lentulus. Governor 01 .J \Idea, to the Roman Senate: A man of average or moderate height, and very distinguished . He has an impressive appearance, so that thosc' who look on him 10\(' and fear him. His hair is the colour of a ripe hazel-nul. It falls straight almost to the level of his ears ; from there down it curls thickly and i~ rather mon° luxuriant, and Lhi, hangs down to his shoulders. In front his hair is paned inLO two, with the parting in the centre in the Nazarene manner. His forehead is wide, smooth and ,t'rem-, and hi~ face is without wrinkles or any marks. It is graced by a slightly reddish tinge, a faint colour. His nose and mouth are faultless. His beard is thick and like a young man's first beard, of the same colour as his hair; it is not particularly long and is parted in the middle. His aspect is simple and mature. His eyes are brilliant, mobile, clear, splendid . He is tenibll' when he reprehends, quiet and kindly when he admonishes. He i~ quick in his movements but always keeps his digDit~'. :--Jo one ever saw him laugh, but h(' has been seen 10 weep. He is hroad in the chest and upstanding; his hands and arms arc fine. In speech he is serious, sparing and modest. He is the most beautiful among the children of men. Not man, paintings contradict this pattern. The Virgin was less consisten t, in spite of the putative portraits by St. Luke, and thf're wa~ an established tradition of discussion about her appearance. There was, lor example, the problem of her complexion: dark or fair. The Dominican Gabriel Barletta gives the traditional view in a sermon on the Virgin's IJeaut)quite a common theme of sermons, though rather symhnlirally approached: You ask: Was the Virgin dark or fair? Albertus Magnus says thal she was 110t simply dark, nor simply red-haired, nor just fair-hairrd . For anyone of these colours by itself brings a certain impnfeclion to a person. This is why onl" says : 'God save me from a red-haired Lombard', r 'God save me from a black-haired German', or 'from a fair-haired Spaniard', or 'from a Bcl~ian of whate\·er colour'. ~1ary wa~ a blend of complexions, partaking of all of thl'm, because a face partaking of al l of I hem is a beautiful one. It is lor this reason medical authorities declare that a complexion compounded of red and fair is best when a third colour i~ added: black. And yet this, says Albertus, we must admit: shl' was a little all the dark side. There are three rea-om for thinkinp; this- firstlv by reason of compit-xion, since Jew.. tend to be dark and ~h(' was aJewess; secondly bv f('ason of witness, since St. Luke made the three pictures of her now at Rom", Loreto and Bologna. and these art brown-complexioned: thirdly, by leaSOI1 or affinitv. A son commollh takes aftcr hi, mothe-T. and \ ice versa; ChTlst was dark, thrrefort. -7