Negatives in written text 251 16 Negatives in written text Adriana Pagano INTRODUCTION Studies of negation have traditionally focused on morphological, syntactic and logical aspects, without considering use or meaning in context, indeed, thexe^haye been relatively few studies dealing with negatives from a >^\gragmatic perspective^ and still fewer attempting to systemize the uses of negaliolirAmohg'tne latter, Tottie (1982, 1987) has proposed a chissifi^ation_ _pf Jhe_uses of negatives in both oral and written language. I collected examples of negatives from written texts and approached my data from three different perspectives, corresponding to the three language functions pointed out by Halliday (see Pagano 1991). From an interpersonal perspective, I analysed the role of negatives in the interaction between writer and reader in order to see why negatives appear in texts. From a textual perspective, I looked at the role of negatives in both the micro- and the macrostructure of the texts. That is, I analysed how negatives relate to adjoining clauses and to the text as a whole. Finally, from an ideational perspective, I compared overt (i.e. negatives having a formal marker of negation such as not, no, nowhere, etc.) and covert negatives (i.e. propositions expressing a negative meaning but having a positive form, such as / forgot), in order to see whether equivalent forms of overt and covert negatives (e.g. / did not remember -1 forgot) represented similar ways of expressing content in language. In the present chapter, I will concentrate on the first of these three perspectives: why do negatives appear in texts? NEGATIVES FROM A PRAGMATIC PERSPECTIVE Before discussing negatives in the interaction between writer and reader, I will first define the object of my study, which is implicit negatives or denials, as Tottie (1987) labels them. What then are implicit negatives or denials? According to Tottie, negatives are used for two main purposes: to reject suggestions (including refusals) to deny assertions from which she draws two categories: 0 Rejections (including Refusals) Denials The main difference between Rejections and Denials, Tottie claims, is that rejections express volition on the part of the sender, for example: A: Would you care for a drink? B: No, thanks. whereas denials do not; they are concerned with facts; they just state that an assertion is not true, for instance: A: So you are still living out there. B: No, I am not. I have rented a flat near the bank. This explanation, however, is not satisfactory in its differentiation of the two negative uses, since it might be argued that volition, a quality associated exclusively with rejections by Tottie, may also underlie denials. That is, there is also volition in expressing a denial. The difference between rejections and denials may be better explained from a func^pnal^perspecjtiye, considering the function which is predominant in each situation. If we regard rejections and denials from the perspective of language function (Halliday 1970, 1973), we note that the language component that predominates in each of these uses is different. In denials, the ideational component is predominant: when we deny something, we are concerned with expressing our view on a particular fact, that is, with whether things are one c, yy. way or another, suchas: «J A: Then finally she got what she wanted. B: Well, I wouldn't say that. She never wanted to break with him. Things just happened that way. B's denial of A's assumption (the woman in question wanted to end her relationship with her boyfriend) has a strong ideational component: B wants to correct A's view of a fact; the truth or correctness of the fact is more relevant than the interpersonal element in the conversation. However, if the conversation went like this: A: So the party is at 9. Shall I bring something to eat or ... ? B: No, thanks. Don't worry. We'll have pizza. In saying 'no', B is assuming a role in the conversation; he is providing an answer to A's offer (interpersonal function). There is certainly an ideational component (A does not need to bring anything to the party), but the jnteracjyLgnal function (a rejection) is the one that predominates. Thus, taking into account the predominant language component in a particular instance of language use, rather than the notion of volition, we can posit in agreement with Tottie that rejections and denials constitute two different categories of negative use. 252 Advances in written text analysis What denials negate, Tottie further states, can be either an explicitly stated assertion, as in There are two kinds of waste producers: those that produce inorganic waste and those that do not. or an assertion that is somehow implicit in the contort of the interaction, generally an assumption by the producer of the denial with respect to his interlocutor's beliefs or expectations, for example: The most significant departure in the CEELT examination is that video recordings are used in the Oral and Listening Comprehension section. These are clips from actual lessons and not specially scripted. For the Oral test the clip acts only as a stimulus to interactive communication in groups of three. (MET, 15 March 1988: 43) In this example, the denial 'not specially scripted' refers to a proposition which has not been explicitly asserted, as would be the case, for instance, if the paragraph had read: In previous tests, the clips were specially scripted by our language specialists; this time they are not. where an assertion is first presented and then denied. In the example taken from MET, the denial refers to an expectation wMchn^Ke writer assumgsJhis reader has concerning the scripts of the tests. At this point, a brief explanatory note concerning Tottie's terminology is necessary. Her terms explicit and implicit denials are perhaps a bit misleading in that what is explicit or implicit is not, as might be expected, the denials themselves, but the^jtfopositions that arej3ejng_denie^. In other words, the explicitness/implicitness criterion used in her classification refers to the thing that is denied and not to the negative itself. Thus, in an exchange like: A: Has the garbage been emptied? B: You know bloody well I've been out all day, how could I have emptied the garbage can? B certainly produces what is commonly called an implicit negative answer, meaning 'No, I haven't done it'; however, it is not what Tottie (1982) considers as jmjrficitjiemgl. Indeed, it is not a denial at all in Tottie's terms, since there is no formal marker of negation, such as no, never, nothing, etc. An implicit denial, according to Tottie, is a denial of a proposition which has not been explicitly formulated in the text. For example: WHY MOSQUITO REPELLENTS REPEL They are not substances that a mosquito somehow finds distasteful. They jam the mosquito's sensors so that it is not able to follow the warm and moist air currents given off by a warm-blooded animal. (Wright 1975: 104) / / ^Negatives in written text 253 Here, the writer is denying what the reader might believe in relation to repellents: they are distasteful to the mosquito. This is an idea implicit in the text, inferable from the text. This is what Tottie calls jmjjjiziulenial. Implicit denials then are denials which originate as a product of an assumption by the producer in relation to his/her interlocutor's beliefs. Being denials of implicit assertions, they reveal aspects of discourse which are not explicit- In other words, they reveal the process going on in the*s Therefore, in cases where certaiixjnformation is non-existent, the writer r "'"teader, all this implies that the writer attributes to his/her ideal reader certain knowledge (schemas) and beliefs or ideas specific to the topic being dealt with. Taking those attributes for granted, the writer can build a message aimed at a target reader. DATA ANALYSIS In order to see how denials appear in this process of text construction, I selected and considered a reasonable number of denials and tried to see which ideas or propositions were denied and whether there was any reason for the writer to deny them. Remember that implicit denials, as their name states, refer to propositions which are not explicit in the text. The fact that they make no reference to an explicit proposition, however, does not mean that they appear out of the blue, without any connection at all to the topic being developed. They occur because there must be some reason why the writer feels the need to use a negative. From the analysis of the data, I extracted four reasons why the writer does this and I classified them into four categories: (1) Denials of background information: that is, denials used when the writer assumes that the reader entertains certain mistaken ideas from his previous background knowledge. (2) Denials of text-processed information: that is, denials used when the writer assumes that the reader could derive a wrong idea from the text. ^ (a) Denials used to prevent an erroneous inference from,text to come. (b) Denials used to correct an idea already processed/in the text. (3) Unfulfilled expectations: that is, denials used when the writer wants to express an unfulfilled expectation of which s/he makes the reader co-participant. (4) Contrasts: that is, denials used to compare or contrast two or more items. In order to clarify these categories, let us consider each of them with examples from my data. Denials of background information In this class, the propositions denied by the writer are ideas which s/he assumes the interlocutor may, irrespective or independent of the text itself, Negatives in written text 259 entertain in connection with some aspect of the topic being dealt with, for instance: Another important point to remember is that sexual orientation is not completely permanent. Especially in adolescence, but also throughout adulthood, sexual orientation can change. (Coleman 1981: 217) The idea that sexual orientation is permanent is attributed to the reader. The writer, being familiar with the topic and with ideas generally held about it, such as the one denied in the example, feels the need,to correct those wrong views through a denial and present his own view afterwards. Similarly in Oat-bran muffins alone aren't going to save you. Eat a high-fiber diet with a variety of foods. Emphasize vegetables, fruit and whole grains. {Runner's World, March 1990: 68) The writer denies a view which gained popularity through mass-media publicity: the miraculous power of oat-bran to reduce cholesterol, and which he knows his audience is likely to entertain. As the wrong idea (from the writer's viewpoint) is a popular and widespread one, he assumes his reader believes or at least is familiar with it. Thus, he must explicitly correct it. The idea denied can also be a specific one (e.g. in academic writing), which only those who are familiar with the basic assumptions and theories of the ^sgeclfic area xan actually have, as they belong to the community which sustains those ideas. Hence in: Design is not art. It is also not engineering, and it is not science. It is time to recognize this and distinguish the differences. Design is not separative, it is integrative. One of the hallmarks of design is its penchant for integration. (Owen 1989: 4) a number of misconceptions about design, which the writer knows his reader may entertain, are denied. For someone outside the field of design, the denials and/or the necessity for them may sometimes not be fully understood. ^ ' This category of denials is the commonest in the data. Here are some more J examples.' a^^j/k-t*,**^ A text is a semantic unit, not a grammatical one. But meanings are realized through wordings ... (Halliday 1985: xvii) Also to learn. Chamorro owes her election not to any natural gift for leadership but to her married name. Though graced with regal poise and an engaging personality, she has had little experience in public life. (TIME, 12 March 1990: 13) One reason is to help you learn new, permanent eating patterns. While restricting your calories certainly will help you lose body fat, weight loss f - / / • r roptt 260 Advances in written text analysis and dieting cannot go on forever. They're merely temporary therapeutic measures to help you attain a desirable body composition. (Runner's World, January 1987: 36) It must be remembered that, as I have already stated, what is denied must be within the range of possibilities that can be plausibly denied (existential paradigm). Thus in / ' He was carrying the .25 when the cops arrested him on the street the following day. He wasn't wearing colors; few members do any more, since gang emblems are as open an invitation to arrest as carrying a semiautomatic rifle. But just the fact that he was dressed in low-slung black trousers, Nikes and Pendleton shirt gave him away. (TIME, 18 June 1990: 22) the statement that the boy was not wearing colours is denying the idea that is generally assumed of a gang: they usually have special or distinctive clothes. In fact, the writer goes on to explain that wearing colours is a practice no longer followed by gang members. Wearing colours is an idea that is plausibly related to gangs. Had the writer said he wasn't eating peanuts, it would certainly have been unexpected, unless the writer later explained that eating peanuts is a usual practice among gangs, that is, unless it were part of the existential paradigm of gangs. V'^,„, „ _ rJi- f>( at-** Denials of text-processed information This class of denials involves propositions (i.e. the ideas or beliefs) which tne writer thinks the reader could wrongly infer from the text. This implies an awareness by the producer of which points in the text will be dubious or ambiguous for the reader. Therefore, out of solidarity with the reader and because the writer is interested in the reader's understanding and eventually supporting his/her view, the writer detects those misleading parts in the text and through denials cancels the wrong inferences, for example: If a male increases his chances of reproduction through this type of cooperation because the favor is returned later on, the behavior is referred to as reciprocal altruism. In many species reciprocal altruism appears to have evolved in response to situations where it is difficult, if not impossible, for a solitary male to successfully mate with a female. This interpretation is not universally accepted. Scott Kraus and John Prescott ... suggest... that the males are not cooperating but rather are competing with one another for access to the female. (Wursig 1988: 81) In this example, the writer presents a theory accounting for the sexual behaviour of whales. The way in which Wursig presents the theory may lead the reader at that point in the text to think the theory is an accepted or probable one. As this is not the case, the writer points out the relativity of the Negatives in written text 261 view presented, denying what he thinks may be the reader's possible wrong inference: that the theory is generally accepted. Within this kind of denial, we can distinguish between (a) and (b): (a) Denials in which the ideas denied may actually be ideas or reactions which the writer anticipates or expects the reader to have in connection with what s/he is going to say in the text, for instance: -.. , A ■ __? , i ' " c 7 don't want to sound sentimental but they've been saving up to come here to see me and they'd see me talk the songs ...' (The Sunday Times, 22 April 1990: 1) Here the speaker cited in the text anticipates the reaction that his words may produce in his interlocutor (the reporter that interviewed him); he denies what he believes the listener will think about him. (b) Denials in which the proposition denied has been suggested by previous parts of the same text as in: 'Relatively few people have applied for studies in the exercise line', says Wood. 'The number's not negligible, but proportionately it's rather small. Drugs are ridiculously over-represented, and that has to reflect the importance of the drug companies . . .' (Runner's World, May 1990: 1) It has been estimated that nearly 50% of recent marriage cohorts will experience marital dissolution .... However, these figures do not necessarily mean a massive rejection of marriage and family life, as most individuals who experience marital dissolution eventually remarry. %\/c.u^+AA--- (Teachman and Heckert, 1985: 185) In these examples, there is some idea in the text which, the writer thinks, is likely to lead the reader to a wrong interpretation. That is why that idea has to be expanded or clarified; for example, if the writer states that graffiti became more elaborate and less vulgar, the reader may very well come to think that from that moment onwards all graffiti were elaborate and critical, which is not true. Hence the writer's cjarificatory denial. Unfulfilled expectations Implicit denials can also represent unfulfilled expectations on the part of the writer and the reader, as the former assumes his/her expectations are also the latter's. Let us consider the following example: To control the development of a plant, light must have some effect on the developmental blueprints, the genes. Yet whereas the biochemical reactions involved in photosynthesis have been described at length, it is not at all -k í ■ 262 Advances in written text analysis ■ 1 clear how light influences the expression of plant genes. Six years ago we set out to clarify the biochemical basis for photomorphogenesis by beginning with the light-responsive genes themselves. (Moses and Chua 1988: 64) The writers here acknowledge some information (the biochemical reactions in photosynthesis have been described at length) but then indicate that some information which for them is relevant and, they assume, for their reader too, is not clear. We could say that the writers have an expectation connected with something that is significant for the field of research and believe that their reader, being someone interested in that field of research, has the same expectation; therefore, they inform the reader about what they expected. It could be claimed that some expectations seem to be the writer's, in which case the denials give the reader access to the writer's own thought processes. However, we must always bear in mind that the writer writes for an ideal reader and the very fact that s/he includes an expression of an unfulfilled expectation in the text may indicate that s/he thinks that information about that unfulfilled expectation (be this missing information or an excuse for not presenting or dealing with some aspect of the topic in question) is relevant for the ideal reader. Similarly, in y cmi^'^ ■ • Bowheads are also believed to feed at the bottom (usually at depths of less than 60 meters), but, it is not clear how, equipped with long and finely fringed baleen, they are able to do so. We have seen bowheads surfacing with muddy water streaming from the sides of the mouth, a behavior that in gray whales is clearly associated with bottom feeding. (Wursig 1988: 79) But Bart doesn't illuminate why Kerkorian does what he does. He offers a few new anecdotes about Kerkorian's gambling habits, but the financier never comes alive. Bart seems content with his conviction that the MGM boss lives simply to be a trader and is not a manager. {Business Week International, 23 July 1990: 8) Generally, an unfulfilled expectation leaves implicit the idea that what is missing, absent, etc., should be otherwise. Sometimes, the writer tries to respond to.expectegjgns wJlufiLarejinly the reader's expectations. That is, the writer did not expect that but thinks the reader probably will. This is clearly seen in prefaces, introductory or aclaratory notes, in which the writer states his/her intention concerning the text and the scope of his/her work. Consider these examples: This article attempts not grand solutions but rather a clarification of some of the theoretical differences between two major camps in the current debates, recognizing that in these debates political commitments often precede and determine theoretical positions. (Valverde 1989: 237) Negatives in written text 263 The purpose of this short section... is to explore a few points prompted by material in the main part of each chapter . . . No attempt is made to be comprehensive and some comments are concerned with areas marginal to the main themes. (Pears 1985: 9) Both writers exempt themselves from presenting information which their readers could otherwise have reasonably expected. Contrasts To this class belong those denials which appear as implicit contrasts between two or more things, for example: For past generations, lifestyle was the leading pharmacopeia. They had no antibiotics, no cures for infectious disease. They had to rely on their manner of living to preserve their health. (Runner's World, February 1990: 16) Here, there is an implicit comparison between the past and the present, and the differences are pointed out. These are actually the denials indicating the absence of antibiotics and cures, which we now have. In About three fourths of the U.S. population is concentrated in urban areas. People growing up in the inner city often have little exposure to or opportunity for leisure/recreation experiences in a natural environment. Adult urbanites, however, are more likely than rural residents to be recreation/leisure users of public outdoor areas. Yet, they were not provided the opportunities during youth to learn the skills and knowledge which would allow them to understand the dynamics of the natural environment. (Journal of Physical Education, Recreation and Dance, April 1990: 49) the comparison takes place between the people living in town and the people living in rural areas. In At Sudbury Valley there is no curriculum. There are no academic requirements. There is no evaluation of students except when requested, no grades or other devices to rank them from best to worst. There is no school-imposed segregation of any kind - not by age, not by sex, not by ability. Students are free to move about at will, using the school's laboratories, workshops, library, playground, and other resources. (Phi Delta Kappa, May 1984: 609) the contrast is established between, traditionahschools and Sudbury school, which claims to be special. 264 Advances in written text analysis Another category? In a small number of cases in the data, denials apparently have a different purpose from those already analysed. These specific denials contain a modal verb meaning possibility and are followed by a restriction which actually opposes them, for instance: Saabs may not look large. Yet the Saab 9000 is the only imported car in the r USA rated 'large' by the Environmental Protection Agency. > ti I'■'<;J\.. (Business Week International, 12 March 1990: 1) 8 Through the denial the writer is actually admitting, or better, conceding the ♦ fact that Saabs do not look large. It is as though he were saying: 'O.K. I agree. Saabs may not look large. But...' And there comes a restriction implying some Saabs are large. Another example is: Solar technology may never eclipse conventional power sources. But it already promises the children of Africa a brighter future. (Business Week International, 23 July 1990: 15) The same process takes place here. The writer admits something but then presents an alternative which reduces the effect of the denial. As the number of examples having similar features to these two examples above is very small, we cannot at the moment formulate or state any features of this category but just point to its potential existence. I CONCLUSIONS In analysing the claim of the writer when producing a denial, we have so far dealt only with the interpersonal perspective of denials, that is, denials in the interaction between writer and reader. We can also approach negatives from a pragmatic perspective and see how denials relate with adjoining clauses. For instance, we can analyse the environments or clause relationships in which denials appear most frequently, as in Denial-Correction, What Lithuania is experiencing, therefore, is not betrayal, nor is it appeasement. It is tragedy. (TIME, 16 April 1990: 52) and see whether the accompanying member of the denial is actually predicted or anticipated by the denial. That is, whether after the denial in the Denial-^J^rrec^nptttterii, we, as readers, expect a correction. From an ideational perspective, we can also ask ourselves whether apparently equivalent forms such as These two insects do not belong to the same species. These two insects belong to different species. I Negatives in written text 265 represent the same way of expressing content in language and for what purposes would one be used instead of the other. A final goal could be to integrate the three perspectives and see the three language components at work in negatives. APPENDIX: TEXTS USED OR REFERRED TO Journals Automatica, 26 June 1989: 815. Business Week International, 12 March 1990: 1; 23 July 1990: 8, 15. Computer Design, July 1983. Journal of Physical Education, Recreation and Dance, April 1990: 49. MET, 15 March 1988: 43. Phi Delta Kappa, May 1984: 609. Runner's World, June 1985: 29; February 1990: 16; March 1990:.68; May 1990: 1. The Sunday Times, 22 April 1990: 1. TIME, 2 April 1990: 46; 16 April 1990: 52. Articles and books Brazil, D. (1985) The Communicative Value of Intonation in English, Discourse Monographs No. 8, Birmingham: University of Birmingham. Cohen, G. et al. (1986) Memory: A Cognitive Approach, Philadelphia: Open University Press. Coleman, E. (1981) 'Counselling adolescent males', The Personnel and Guidance Journal (December): 215-18. Current, R. and G. Goodwin (1975) A History of the United States to 1877, New York: Alfred Knopf. Halliday, M. A. K. (1970) 'Language structure and language function', in J. Lyons (ed.), New Horizons in Linguistics, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 140-65. - (1983) Explorations in the Functions of Language, London: Edward Arnold. - (1985) An Introduction to Functional Grammar, London: Edward Arnold. Miller, G. and P. Johnson-Laird (1976) Language and Perception, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ° ' ~*j Moses, P. H. and N. Chua (1988) 'Light switches for plant genes', Scientific American 258/4 (April): 64-9. Owen, C. H. (1989) 'Design education in the information age', a speech given at Korea Institute of Technology's Exposition and Design, 20 November, Seoul. Pagano, A. (1991) 'A pragmatic study of negatives in written text', unpublished MA diss., Florian6polis: Universidade Ferderal de Santa Catarina. Pears, N. (1985) Basic Biogeography, London: Longman. Quirk, R. et al. (1985) A Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language, London, Longman. Teachman, J. and A. Heckert (1985) 'The impact of age and children on remarriage', Journal of Family Issues 6/2 (June): 185-203. Tottie, G. (1982) 'Where do negatives come from?', Studio Linguistica 36/1: 88-105. - (1987) 'Rejections, denials and explanatory statements - a reply to Fretheim', Studia Linguistica 41/2: 154-63. Valverde, M. (1989) 'Beyond gender dangers and private pleasures: theory and ethics in the sex debates', Feminist Studies 15/2: 237-54. Widdowson, H. G. (1979) Explorations in Applied Linguistics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wright, R. (1975) 'Why mosquito repellents repel', Scientific American 233/1 (July): 104-11. Wursig, B. (1988) "The behavior of Baleen whales', Scientific American 258/4 (April) 78-85. t-LL