arXiv:1206.1203v2[math.CT]4Jul2012 A COLIMIT DECOMPOSITION FOR HOMOTOPY ALGEBRAS IN CAT JOHN BOURKE Abstract. Badzioch showed that in the category of simplicial sets each homotopy algebra of a Lawvere theory is weakly equivalent to a strict algebra. In seeking to extend this result to other contexts Rosick´y observed a key point to be that each homotopy colimit in SSet admits a decomposition into a homotopy sifted colimit of finite coproducts, and asked the author whether a similar decomposition holds in the 2-category of categories Cat. Our purpose in the present paper is to show that this is the case. 1. Introduction When V is a complete and cocomplete symmetric monoidal closed category the theory of categories enriched in V develops in much the same way as ordinary category theory. Classical concepts, such as finite limit theories and their algebras, have enriched analogues: if T is a small V-category with finite products one can consider T-algebras in V, which are V-functors X : T → V preserving finite products. If V has a notion of weak equivalence then algebras have a natural homotopy analogue: a homotopy algebra being given by a V-functor X : T → V which preserves products up to weak equivalence, in the sense that the canonical map X(A1 × . . . × An) → X(A1) × . . . × X(An) is a weak equivalence for each finite tuple of objects of T. Each genuine or strict algebra is a homotopy algebra and one can ask to what extent the converse is true—with respect to the natural pointwise notion of weak equivalence one can ask whether each homotopy algebra is weakly equivalent to a strict one. Badzioch in [2] investigated this question in the case of simplicially enriched categories, with theories the classical single sorted Lawvere theories viewed as discrete simplicial categories; his main result a rigidification theorem establishing each homotopy algebra to be weakly equivalent to a strict algebra. This result was extended by Bergner in [3] to cover finite product theories, again in the simplicial setting. In [22] Rosick´y has investigated the possibility of extending these rigidification results to other settings, by allowing his base of enrichment V to be a monoidal model category other than simplicial sets, and by considering weighted limit theories more general than finite product theories. One of his rigidification results, Theorem 3.3 of [22], requires that each cofibrant weight, or cofibrant object in Date: July 5, 2012. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary: 18D05, 55P99. Supported by the Grant agency of the Czech Republic under the grant P201/12/G028. 1 2 JOHN BOURKE [J, V] with its projective model structure, admits a certain kind of colimit decomposition. He asked the author whether such a colimit decomposition exists in the case that V = Cat with weak equivalences the equivalences of categories, and when the theories under consideration are just finite product theories—the special nature of the colimit decomposition now requiring that each cofibrant object of [J, Cat] can be presented as a sifted colimit of finite coproducts of representables, in which moreover each colimit involved is homotopically well behaved in a manner described in Section 4.2. The aim of the present paper is to show, in Theorem 8, that this is the case. With this result in place Rosick´y’s theorems’ 3.3 and 5.1 of [22] yield rigidification results for homotopy algebras of finite product theories in Cat—his Theorem 5.1 now asserts that, in Cat, each homotopy algebra of a finite product theory is weakly equivalent to a strict algebra, a direct analogue of the results in the simplicial setting described above. Now the cofibrant objects of [J, Cat] are the flexible weights of [4]. Flexible limits and colimits have been the subject of much study in 2-category theory, and many of the results required to give the main decomposition, in Theorem 8, are known— our main contribution here is to put these facts together in an appropriate way. Since the results are spread throughout the literature on 2-category theory, and some without detailed proof, we give a thorough, and reasonably self contained, treatment of all aspects involved in the decomposition, with the intention of making Rosick´y’s rigidification result in this 2-categorical setting more easily accessible. In Section 2 we give the necessary background, beginning with a few brief remarks on weighted limits and colimits. We recall the notion of a flexible weight, and so flexible limits and colimits, describing the connection with model categories. Examples of flexible colimits are given and their properties discussed. We begin the third section by describing those flexible colimits involved in our decomposition of a flexible weight, giving a detailed treatment of reflexive codescent and reflexive lax codescent objects. We show each of these colimits to be sifted colimits—the case of reflexive codescent objects is in [15]. Combining these results a presentation of each flexible weight as a sifted flexible colimit of coproducts of representables is given—this is the main novel result of the paper. In the final section we begin by discussing bicolimits and their relationship with ordinary colimits. We use that filtered colimits are bicolimits in Cat [19] and reduce from arbitrary coproducts of representables to finite coproducts, giving the final decomposition in Theorem 8. The author thanks Jiˇr´ı Rosick´y and Stephen Lack for useful discussions on the content of this paper. 2. Weighted colimits and flexible colimits 2.1. Weighted colimits. When V is a complete and cocomplete symmetric monoidal closed category one has the full theory of categories enriched in V [11]. V itself admits such an enrichment (which we will also denote by V) and for each small V-category J we have the enriched category [J, V] whose objects, V-functors, are called J-indexed weights. Given a diagram D : J → C its W-weighted limit is an object {W, D} together with a V-natural transformation W → C({W, D}, D−) A COLIMIT DECOMPOSITION FOR HOMOTOPY ALGEBRAS IN CAT 3 called a cone, or cylinder, which induces an isomorphism C(A, {W, D}) ∼= [J, V](W, C(A, D−)) for each A ∈ C. Dually given a diagram D : Jop → C its W-weighted colimit, or just W-colimit to be brief, is an object W ⋆ D equipped with a cocone W → C(D−, W ⋆ D) inducing an isomorphism C(W ⋆ D, A) ∼= [J, V](W, C(D−, A)) for each A ∈ C. Amongst weighted colimits we find the familiar conical colimits such as coequalisers and coproducts, and also tensors by objects of V, but also more complex kinds—for instance when V = Cat we have codescent objects, Kleisli objects of monads and many other useful colimits, some of which are described in detail in Section 3. 2.2. Flexible colimits and cofibrancy. A limit {W, D} or colimit W ⋆D is said to be flexible if W is a flexible weight. One can approach flexible weights using model categories without knowing anything of 2-category theory beyond general enriched category theory, and likewise using 2-category theory without any model categories at all. Both perspectives are important here so we recall each. Flexible weights were first defined in 2-category theory, as a special case of the notion of flexible algebra for a 2-monad, and the results we describe now are special cases of results of [5] concerning 2-monads. Whilst the generality of 2-monads is mostly beyond our needs at present a little background is required. Given a 2-category C we have the identity on objects inclusion ι : [J, C] → Ps(J, C) with the latter 2-category having 2-functors as objects, arrows the more general pseudonatural transformations, and modifications for 2-cells. The inclusion is the identity on objects so that we typically omit to label its action. If C is both complete and cocomplete the inclusion has a left adjoint Q—we refer the reader to Section 3.2 for more detail on this. The unit and counit at W ∈ [J, C] are given by pseudonatural and 2-natural transformations pW : W QW and qW : QW → W respectively. The isomorphism [J, C](QW, X) ∼= Ps(J, C)(W, X) exhibits QW as a pseudomorphism classifier, in the sense that any pseudonatural W X factors uniquely through pW : W QW as a 2-natural transformation. One of the triangle equations for the adjunction asserts that the pseudonatural pW : W QW is a section of qW in Ps(J, C); in fact qW is a retract equivalence, or surjective equivalence, in the 2-category Ps(J, C). It follows in particular that the component of qW : QW → W at each j ∈ J is a surjective equivalence in C; thus qW is a pointwise surjective equivalence. Now let us interpret the above in the special case of [J, Cat]. We have seen that the counit qW : QW → W at a weight W always admits a pseudonatural section pW ; the weight W is said to be a flexible weight [4] just when qW admits a section in [J, Cat], in which case qW : QW → W is in fact a surjective equivalence in [J, Cat]. On the other hand if we ignore its 2-dimensional structure then Cat is a combinatorial model category with weak equivalences and fibrations the equivalences 4 JOHN BOURKE of categories and isofibrations, and trivial fibrations the surjective equivalences. Cartesian product gives it the structure of a monoidal model category [9] so that one can speak of model 2-categories, Cat being one of these. It was shown in [16] that [J, Cat] obtains the projective model structure in which the weak equivalences and fibrations are pointwise as in Cat, and that a flexible weight is just a cofibrant object, or cofibrant weight, therein. This was done in the more general context of 2-dimensional monad theory, but since the proof is short we include it in the case of weights. Proposition 1. (Lack) When [J, Cat] is equipped with the projective model structure, the cofibrant objects therein are exactly the flexible weights. Proof. In the projective model structure on [J, Cat] the trivial fibrations are pointwise as in Cat, and so the pointwise surjective equivalences. We have seen that qW : QW → W is one of these; as such it will exhibit QW as a cofibrant replacement of W if we can show QW to be cofibrant. Upon doing so it is clear that W will be cofibrant just when qW admits a section, which is to say when W is a flexible weight. To see that QW is cofibrant suppose that f : X → Y is a pointwise surjective equivalence—given an arbitrary arrow r : QW → Y we should show it factors through f. Observe that as f is a pointwise surjective equivalence it admits a pseudonatural section g : Y X so that fg = 1. Now consider the following diagram W QW Y X pW ///o/o/o/o r // f  gr ;;;{;{;{;{;{;{ h .. where all but h have been defined. By the universal property of pW the composite grpW : W X is uniquely of the form hpW for a 2-natural h : QW → X. Now to check that fh = r it suffices, by the same universal property, to show fhpW = rpW But we have fhpW = fgrpW = rpW as required. Knowing that the flexible weights are the cofibrant weights doesn’t offer much insight as to what they actually look like, or why they are interesting in 2-category theory. Let us conclude this section by briefly mentioning some examples of flexible colimits including the generating ones, and some other properties. We will describe the examples of most importance in more detail in Section 3. 2.3. Pseudocolimits. Given a weight W and diagram D : Jop → C its W weighted pseudocolimit W ⋆p D is defined by an isomorphism C(W ⋆p D, A) ∼= Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)) natural in A. By the adjunction Q ⊣ ι we have a natural isomorphism [J, Cat](QW, C(D−, A)) ∼= Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)) so that the pseudocolimit is nothing but the weighted colimit QW ⋆ D. That pseudocolimits are flexible is easy to see: the adjunction Q ⊣ ι generates a comonad (Q, q, ∆) on [J, Cat] with counit the same q : Q → 1 as before; in particular each QW admits a (co-free) coalgebra structure, and so is certainly a flexible weight. Since the pseudocolimit W ⋆p D is the genuine colimit of D weighted by a cofibrant replacement A COLIMIT DECOMPOSITION FOR HOMOTOPY ALGEBRAS IN CAT 5 of W, pseudocolimits are closely related to homotopy colimits—this relationship was studied in [8]. 2.4. Saturation, pie colimits and splittings of idempotents. Let Flex denote the class of flexible weights so that Flex(J) ⊂ [J, Cat] consists of the J-indexed flexible weights. It was shown in [4] that the flexible weights form a saturated class1 in the sense of [14]. This means that, for each J, Flex(J) contains the representables and is closed in [J, Cat] under flexible colimits (not just J-indexed ones). Moreover four kinds of colimit suffice to construct all flexible weights—namely co(p)roducts, co(i)nserters, co(e)quifiers and (s)plittings of idempotents, by which we mean that these four colimits are flexible and Flex(J) = PIES∗(J), the closure of the representables in [J, Cat] under these four kinds of colimit. It follows that if one can construct W-colimits out of these four kinds in a general 2-category then W is flexible: one uses that W = W ⋆Y for the Yoneda embedding Y and carries out the corresponding construction in [J, Cat]. This fact provides a convenient way to test whether a particular weight is flexible—examples which are easily seen to be flexible in this manner are coinverters, Kleisli objects of monads, the codescent objects of the following section along with numerous others—many such cases were described in [12] and [4]. Though not relevant in what follows it is perhaps worth mentioning that if we drop splittings of idempotents from the above and take the closure PIE∗(J) ⊂ [J, Cat] we get what are called the pie weights [20]. Apart from splittings of idempotents essentially all flexible colimits, such as those just mentioned, are pie. The pie weights can be recognised as precisely those admitting coalgebra structure for the comonad Q on [J, Cat]—see [18] or [6]—this can be interpreted as saying that they are the algebraically cofibrant objects in [J, Cat] in the sense of [21], a perspective which was further explored in [6]. 2.5. The importance of flexible limits and colimits in 2-category theory. Let us briefly indicate some reasons for the interest in flexibility. Primary objects of study in 2-dimensional universal algebra are 2-categories, such as the 2-category of monoidal categories and strong monoidal functors, whose morphisms only preserve structure up to isomorphism. Such 2-categories generally admit pie limits [5], and if the structure involved is itself “flexible”, such as monoidal structure, they also admit flexible limits [4]; note that in the full sub 2-category containing the more “rigid” strict monoidal categories idempotents need not split. The precise distinction is that monoidal categories are the algebras for a flexible 2-monad [10, 5] whereas strict monoidal categories are not. 3. Sifted flexible colimits and a first decomposition A weight W ∈ [J, Cat] is said to be sifted if finite products commute with Wcolimits in Cat. This is to say that the 2-functor W ⋆− : [Jop, Cat] → Cat preserves finite products. In the present section we describe a number of weights which are both sifted and flexible and give our first decomposition result. The two key kinds of colimits are reflexive codescent and reflexive lax codescent objects—that the former are sifted is a result of Lack, Proposition 4.3 of [15], 1Saturated classes were originally called closed in [1]. 6 JOHN BOURKE though the proof only outlined. We fill in the details here and follow a suggestion of Lack to extend this result to the lax setting. In both cases we follow the argument outlined in [15]—to apply the following lemma2 of the same paper, which reduces the colimits to be computed to manageable special cases. Lemma 2. (Lack) A weight W : J → Cat is sifted if W ⋆ − : [Jop, Cat] → Cat preserves finite products of representables. If J has a terminal object which is preserved by W then W is sifted so long as W ⋆ − preserves binary products of representables. Let us remark upon our terminology concerning codescent objects—this is based upon [15] and fits well with the appearance of codescent objects in 2-dimensional monad theory. What we call lax codescent and codescent objects have also been called codescent and isocodescent objects respectively—see [23] for instance. We will only consider the notion of a reflexive lax codescent or reflexive codescent object here which relate to the irreflexive kind [15] as reflexive coequalisers do to coequalisers—a notable distinction is that only the reflexive variants commute with finite products in Cat and Set respectively. 3.1. Reflexive lax codescent objects. Truncating the simplicial category ∆ at the ordered set with three elements gives a full subcategory ∆2 ⊂ ∆; now restricting the usual embedding ∆ → Cat along the inclusion yields the weight Wl : ∆2 → Cat for reflexive lax codescent objects. A diagram ∆op 2 → C in a 2-category C consists of a truncated simplicial object as on the left below (1) A2 A1 A0 d // ioo c // p // m // q //roo loo A1 A0 A A0 d <<②②② c ""❊❊❊ f ""❊❊❊ f <<②②② η  In elementary terms its reflexive lax codescent object A is specified by a triple (A, f : A0 → A, η : fd ⇒ fc) as above satisfying the two equations for a lax codescent cocone. The first of these asserts the equality A2 A1 A0 A A0 A1 A1 p BB☎☎☎☎☎ q ✿✿✿✿✿ d // c // d BB☎☎☎☎☎ c ✿✿✿✿✿ f ✿✿✿✿✿✿ f BB☎☎☎☎☎☎ m // η  = A2 A0 A0 A A0 A1 A1 p BB☎☎☎☎☎ q ✿✿✿✿✿ d // c // c ✿✿✿✿✿ d BB☎☎☎☎☎ f // f ✿✿✿✿✿✿ f BB☎☎☎☎☎☎ η  η  whilst the second equation asserts that ηi : f = fdi ⇒ fci = f is an identity 2-cell. As with all 2-categorical colimits it has both a 1 and 2-dimensional aspect to its universal property; the 1-dimensional aspect asserts that given any other such cocone (B, g, θ) there exists a unique arrow g′ : A → B such that g′f = g and 2 In [15] the hypothesis on the terminal object does not appear in the statement of the lemma but is discussed in the proof. A COLIMIT DECOMPOSITION FOR HOMOTOPY ALGEBRAS IN CAT 7 g′η = θ; the 2-dimensional aspect asserts that given a second such triple (B, h, φ) together with a 2-cell ρ : g ⇒ h rendering the square gd gc hd hc θ +3 ρd  ρc  φ +3 commutative, then there exists a unique 2-cell ρ′ : g′ ⇒ h′ between the induced factorisations such that ρ′ ◦ f = ρ. The most important example of such colimits for our concerns is the following example from [23]. A small category A can be presented as an internal category in Set by taking its truncated nerve. The reader can interpret diagram (1) above in this manner, so that A0, A1 and A2 are the sets of objects, arrows and composable pairs of A, with the maps d and c the domain and codomain projections, and so on. Viewing each of these sets as discrete categories one can view this internal category in Set as an internal category in Cat whose reflexive lax codescent object is exactly A. The universal cocone (A, f, η) has f : A0 → A the identity on objects inclusion, and η : fd ⇒ fc the natural transformation whose component ηα at an object α : x → y ∈ A1 is simply α : x = fdα → fcα = y itself, now viewed as an arrow of A. We leave to the reader the worthwhile exercise of checking that this is indeed the claimed colimit. In order to see that reflexive lax codescent objects are sifted colimits in Cat it will be worth being precise about the manner in which we passed from the category A to the corresponding internal category in Cat; this was achieved by taking the singular functor Cat → [∆op 2 , Set] associated to the embedding ∆2 → Cat and postcomposing by D∗ : [∆op 2 , Set] → [∆op 2 , Cat] where D : Set → Cat is the functor viewing each set as a discrete category; let us write Nd : Cat → [∆op 2 , Cat] for the composite functor (note that this is not a 2-functor). As a composite of limit preserving functors we observe that Nd preserves limits. Consider the 2-functor Wl ⋆ − : [∆op 2 , Cat] → Cat which takes reflexive lax codescent objects and write (Wl ⋆−)0 : [∆op 2 , Cat] → Cat for its underlying functor. The content of our example is that we have an isomorphism Wl ⋆ Nd(A) ∼= A for each category A; moreover this is easily seen to be a natural isomorphism (Wl ⋆ −)0 ◦ Nd ∼= 1. A diagram X ∈ [∆op 2 , Cat] lies in the essential image of Nd just when it is an internal category in Cat with each X(j) discrete; let us call such diagrams in Cat pointwise discrete categories. The relevance of this notion is that the representables ∆2(−, i) : ∆op 2 → Cat, corresponding to our weight Wl : ∆2 → Cat, all share this form. To see this let i ∈ {0, 1, 2} and consider the following composite ∆op 2 ∆op Set Cat j // ∆(−,i) // D // In the middle the representable ∆(−, i) is well known to be the nerve of a category, so that its restriction ∆(−, i) ◦ j is one too. As ∆2 is a full subcategory of ∆ so the restriction ∆(−, i) ◦ j is just ∆2(−, i) which is hence an internal category. But we are supposed to be considering ∆2 as a 2-category and its Cat-valued representables; however since ∆2 is locally discrete the corresponding Cat-valued 8 JOHN BOURKE representable is just the composite D ◦ ∆2(−, i), which, as D preserves pullbacks, is a pointwise discrete category in Cat. We can now prove: Proposition 3. Reflexive lax codescent objects are sifted flexible colimits. Proof. Reflexive lax codescent objects can be constructed by forming a coinserter followed by two coequifiers and are consequently flexible colimits (see 2.4)—this construction is described in Proposition 2.1 of [15] for a more general kind of lax codescent object. With regards siftedness observe that ∆2 has a terminal object preserved by its inclusion to Cat so that it suffices, by Lemma 2, to show that Wl ⋆− : [∆op 2 , Cat] → Cat preserves binary products of representables. Each representable is a pointwise discrete category—we will show Wl ⋆− preserves binary products of these instead. To show Wl ⋆− preserves the product X ×Y of such a pair it suffices to show that its underlying functor (Wl ⋆ −)0 does so. But now X and Y lie in the essential image of Nd so that, as Cat has products and Nd preserves them, the product also lies in the essential image. Consequently we need only show that the composite (Wl⋆−)0◦Nd preserves binary products. Being naturally isomorphic to the identity functor this is the case. 3.2. Reflexive codescent objects. The weight Wi : ∆2 → Cat for reflexive codescent objects is obtained from the weight Wl : ∆2 → Cat for reflexive lax codescent objects by postcomposing Wl by the reflection Cat → Gpd to groupoids, and then passing back via the inclusion Gpd → Cat. In elementary terms, given a diagram as in (1), its reflexive codescent object is specified by a triple (A, f, η) satisfying the same equations as in the lax case, with the exception that η is now required to be an invertible 2-cell; moreover the 1-dimensional universal property of A only quantifies over triples (B, g, θ) in which θ is invertible, whilst the 2dimensional universal property is the same as before. The relevant example concerns the construction of the pseudomorphism classifier QX of a diagram X : J → C in a complete and cocomplete 2-category C as arises from the adjunction (ι : [J, C] ⇆ Ps(J, C) : Q) discussed in 2.2. To explain how this goes observe that restriction U : [J, C] → [obJ, C] along the inclusion of the discrete 2-category with the same objects as C has a left 2-adjoint F and that U is moreover monadic. The adjunction (ǫ, F ⊣ U, η) gives FU the structure of a comonad on [J, C] and so, in the usual way, yields for each X ∈ [J, C] a (truncated) simplicial object (FU)3X (FU)2X FUX ǫF UX // F ηUX oo F UǫX // // // // oo oo where we have omitted to label the higher face and degeneracy maps. The reflexive codescent object of this diagram in [J, C] is exactly QX. That this is the case is best understood in terms of two dimensional monad theory: the monadic adjunction F ⊣ U induces a 2-monad T = UF whose 2category of strict algebras and strict morphisms T-Algs is [J, C] whilst the Tpseudomorphisms, as belonging to the 2-category T-Alg, are precisely the pseudonatural transformations of Ps(J, C)—this is shown in Section 6.6 of [5]. It follows A COLIMIT DECOMPOSITION FOR HOMOTOPY ALGEBRAS IN CAT 9 that the inclusion [J, C] → Ps(J, C) coincides with the inclusion T-Algs → T-Alg that views each strict T-algebra morphism as a pseudomorphism. The formula for QD above is then a special case of the formula for the pseudomorphism classifier QA of a T-algebra A as a reflexive codescent object of free algebras. This formula was first described in [15] in a more general setting relevant to pseudoalgebras—a description better suited to the present level of generality is given in Section 4.2 of [17]. The most important case for us is when C = Cat—at a weight W the above presentation exhibits QW as a reflexive codescent object of free weights. In understanding that reflexive codescent objects are sifted colimits in Cat it will be useful to break down their construction into two steps: as a reflexive lax codescent object followed by a coinverter. It is not worth the effort to describe the weight for coinverters here—see [12]—it suffices to say that the domain 2-category consists of a single 2-cell, so that, correspondingly, one forms the coinverter of a 2-cell α ∈ C(A, B)(f, g) in a 2-category C; this consisting of a pair (C, h) as on the left below A B C f  g AAα  h // A1 A0 A A0 B d <<②②② c ""❊❊❊ f ""❊❊❊ f <<②②② η  f <<②②② g // in which hα is invertible; the 1-dimensional universal property is that given any k : B → D with kα invertible there exists a unique k′ : C → D such that k′h = k; its 2-dimensional universal property asserts that, for each object D, the induced functor C(h, D) : C(C, D) → C(B, D) is fully faithful. Now it is easily seen that given a diagram as in (1) we can form its reflexive codescent object in two steps—firstly forming the reflexive lax codescent object (A, f, η) and then the coinverter (B, g) of the resulting 2-cell η, as drawn on the right above. In the following proposition we shall use this construction to show that reflexive codescent objects are sifted colimits in Cat; however it is not the case that coinverters are themselves sifted, but only reflexive coinverters—this was shown using a 3×3 argument in [13]. The distinction between a reflexive coinverter and a coinverter is in the input; a coinverter is said to be reflexive when the input 2-cell α, as above, admits a splitting, in the sense of an arrow k : B → A such that fk = 1, gk = 1 and αk = 1. We need one further auxiliary concept—that of a liberal arrow. An arrow f : A → B of a 2-category C is said to be liberal if it is conservative in Cop—this means that a 2-cell α : g ⇒ h ∈ C(B, C) out of B is invertible whenever the composite αf is. We will have use for the fact that each bijective on objects functor is liberal in Cat. Finally observe that given a diagram D A B C f  g AAα  h //e // with e liberal then h exhibits C as the coinverter of α if and only if it exhibits C as the coinverter of αe; this follows from the fact that for any r : B → E the composite rα is invertible just when rαe is. With this in place we can prove: 10 JOHN BOURKE Proposition 4. (Lack) Reflexive codescent objects are sifted flexible colimits. Proof. That reflexive codescent objects are flexible follows from their construction via reflexive lax codescent objects and coinverters, both of which are flexible colimits. That coinverters are flexible, constructible from coinserters and coequifiers, can be found in Proposition 4.2 of [12]. With regards siftedness observe that the weights Wi and Wl have the same domain so that the associated representables coincide—these are pointwise discrete categories as in 3.1. Again Wi preserves the terminal object so that, as in the proof of Propostion 3, Wi will be sifted if we can show that the composite (Wi ⋆−)0 ◦Nd : Cat → [∆op 2 , Cat] → Cat preserves binary products. We will show this to be true by breaking this functor down into several components. Given A ∈ Cat the reflexive codescent object of NdA is obtained by forming the reflexive lax codescent object of NdA—this is just (A, f, η) as described in 3.1—followed by the coinverter (B, g) of η as on the left below A1 A0 A A0 B d <<②②② c ""❊❊❊ f ""❊❊❊ f <<②②② η  f <<②②② g // A1 A2 A B t // λ  p  q ?? g // Let us form the arrow category A2 of A which comes equipped with an evident pair of projections and natural transformation λ : p ⇒ q ∈ Cat(A2, A) with the universal property that any natural transformation into A factors uniquely through it; we factorise η as λt accordingly as indicated on the right above. Explicitly t is given by the map which assigns to an object of A1, an arrow of A, the corresponding object of the arrow category A2; thus t is bijective on objects. As such it is liberal so that the coinverter B of η is equally the coinverter of λ. Therefore (Wi ⋆ −)0 ◦ Nd : Cat → [∆op 2 , Cat] → Cat is equally just the functor which first assigns to a category A the 2-cell (A2, λ : p ⇒ q, A) and then its coinverter; certainly the first assignment preserves products since arrow categories are limits (cotensors with the free arrow) in Cat. Furthermore the 2-cell λ is reflexive, split by the functor i : A → A2 that assigns to an object of A the identity arrow upon it; since reflexive coinverters commute with finite products we deduce the claim. 3.3. Decomposition of a flexible weight as a sifted flexible colimit of coproducts of representables. As well as using the above kinds of codescent object in the following decomposition, we will also split an idempotent. Splittings of idempotents are of course absolute colimits and so sifted; and flexible as discussed in 2.4. With these results in place we give our first decomposition. Theorem 5. Each flexible weight lies in the closure of the coproducts of representables under sifted flexible colimits. Proof. If W is a flexible weight then qW : QW → W has a section w : W → QW so that W is the splitting of the idempotent w ◦ qW on QW, a sifted flexible colimit. Now recall from 3.2 the adjunction (U : [J, Cat] ⇆ [obJ, Cat] : F) given by restriction and left Kan extension along the inclusion obJ → J. As described in 3.2 the weight QW is a reflexive codescent object of free weights, those of the form A COLIMIT DECOMPOSITION FOR HOMOTOPY ALGEBRAS IN CAT 11 FX for a family X : obJ → Cat, and so a sifted flexible colimit of free weights by Proposition 4. For j ∈ J each category Xj is, by 3.1, the reflexive lax codescent object of its truncated nerve Nd(Xj) as (unlabelled) on the left below X(j)2 X(j)1 X(j)0 // oo // // // // oo oo X2 X1 X0 // oo // // // // oo oo so that X is the reflexive lax codescent object in [obJ, Cat] of the diagram on the right which pointwise evaluates to that on the left. Applying the left adjoint F : [obJ, Cat] → [J, Cat] we deduce that FX is a reflexive lax codescent object of the FXi, in particular a sifted flexible colimit of the FXi by Proposition 3. For each i ∈ {0, 1, 2} the family Xi : obJ → Cat takes its values amongst the discrete categories. Any Y : obJ → Cat with this property is the coproduct Y = ΣjY (j).obJ(j, −) where, since obJ is discrete, the representable obJ(j, −) is just the characteristic function at j. By the left Kan extension formula for F it is easy to see that F(obJ(j, −)) = J(j−), whence FY = F(ΣjY (j).obJ(j, −)) = ΣjY (j).J(j, −) is a coproduct of representables; in particular for each i ∈ {0, 1, 2} the weight F(Xi) is a coproduct of representables. Thus W can be formed in three steps by taking sifted flexible colimits of coproducts of representables. 4. Filtered colimits and the reduction to finite coproducts In this final section we extend the decomposition of Theorem 5, using filtered colimits to reduce from arbitrary coproducts of representables to finite coproducts. Whilst filtered colimits are not flexible in general they do exhibit some good homotopical behaviour in Cat which is crucial for our decomposition—namely, they are bicolimits in Cat. 4.1. Bicolimits. Given a weight W : J → Cat and diagram D : Jop → C the W-bicolimit W ⋆b D [12] is specified by a pseudococone W C(D−, W ⋆b D) ∈ Ps(J, Cat) such that the induced functor C(W ⋆b D, A) → Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)) is an equivalence for each A ∈ C. The bicolimit is only determined up to equivalence by its defining property; the pseudocolimit, if it exists, provides a canonical instance. We call a genuine colimit W ⋆ D a bicolimit if its colimiting cocone W → C(D−, W ⋆ D) in fact exhibits W ⋆ D as the W-bicolimit. This amounts to saying that the composite C(W ⋆ D, A) ∼= [J, Cat](W, C(D−, A)) → Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)) is an equivalence for each A ∈ C. Since the first component is an isomorphism this is equally to say that the inclusion [J, Cat](W, C(D−, A)) → Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)) is an equivalence for each A ∈ C. If W is flexible then qW : QW → W is an equivalence in [J, Cat] so that q∗ W : [J, Cat](W, C(D−, A)) → [J, Cat](QW, C(D−, A)) is an equivalence for each 12 JOHN BOURKE A. Composing this map with the canonical isomorphism [J, Cat](QW, C(D−, A)) ∼= Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)) yields the above inclusion, so that any flexible colimit is a bicolimit. It is not true that filtered colimits are flexible nor that they are bicolimits in each 2-category. They are, however, bicolimits in Cat—this was shown in Lemma 5.4.9 of [19] by directly calculating filtered colimits in Cat. We give a different proof below, which follows easily from the equivalence of (1) and (3) in the following. Proposition 6. Let C be a complete and cocomplete 2-category consider a weight W ∈ [J, Cat]. The following are equivalent. (1) W-colimits are bicolimits in C. (2) For each diagram D the map qW ⋆ D : QW ⋆ D → W ⋆ D is an equivalence in C. (3) For each pointwise equivalence f : D → E of diagrams the induced W ⋆ D → W ⋆ E is an equivalence in C. Proof. To say that qW ⋆ D : QW ⋆ D → W ⋆ D is an equivalence is equally to say that the functor C(qW ⋆ D, A) : C(W ⋆ D, A) → C(QW ⋆ D, A) is an equivalence for each A ∈ C. The canonical isomorphisms render this isomorphic to the inclusion [J, Cat](W, C(D−, A)) → Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)) so that (1) and (2) are equivalent. That (1) implies (3) is also straightforward. Assuming (1) consider a pointwise equivalence f : D → E of diagrams in [Jop, C]. This induces a pointwise equivalence f∗ : C(E−, A) → C(D−, A) ∈ [J, Cat]. Whiskering by f∗ induces a commutative square [J, Cat](W, C(E−, A)) Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(E−, A)) [J, Cat](W, C(D−, A)) Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)) //   // in which the horizontal arrows are the inclusions, both of which are equivalences since W-colimits are bicolimits in C. The pointwise equivalence f∗ is a genuine equivalence in Ps(J, Cat) so that the right vertical arrow is an equivalence whence, by 2 out of 3, the left vertical arrow is an equivalence too. Therefore the isomorphic C(W ⋆ f, A) : C(W ⋆ E, A) → C(W ⋆ D, A) is an equivalence for each A so that W ⋆ f is itself an equivalence. It remains to show that (3) implies (2). Recall the adjunction (ι : [J, C] ⇆ Ps(J, C) : Qc) from 2.2 with counit qc : Qc → 1. The key point here is that we have an isomorphism λ : QW ⋆ D ∼= W ⋆ QcD compatible with the counits in the sense that the triangle QW ⋆ D W ⋆ QcD W ⋆ Dλ  W ⋆qc D 33❢❢❢❢❢❢❢❢❢ qW ⋆D ++❳❳❳❳❳❳❳❳❳ commutes. This is just the colimit variant of a result on limits of [8]. To see where the isomorphism comes from recall that the cotensor AX (or power) of an object A ∈ C by a category X is the limit defined by a natural isomorphism C(B, AX ) ∼= Cat(X, C(B, A)) A COLIMIT DECOMPOSITION FOR HOMOTOPY ALGEBRAS IN CAT 13 Given a weight W : J → Cat and diagram D : Jop → C this isomorphism extends in a pointwise manner to a natural isomorphism as on the left below [Jop , C](D, AW − ) ∼= [J, Cat](W, C(D−, A)) which, moreover, is compatible with pseudonatural transformations in the sense that Ps(Jop, C)(D, AW −) ∼= Ps(J, Cat)(W, C(D−, A)). Applying these isomorphisms back and forth, together with the universal properties of QW and QcD, yields an isomorphism [J, Cat](QW, C(D−, A)) ∼= [J, Cat](W, C(QcD−, A)) and so the claimed λ : QW ⋆ D ∼= W ⋆ QcD. It is straightforward to check compatibility with the counit. As discussed in 2.2 the map qc D is always a pointwise equivalence so that, by assumption, W ⋆ qc D is an equivalence. As λ is an isomorphism it follows that qW ⋆ D is an equivalence for each D proving (2). Corollary 7. (Makkai-Par´e) Filtered colimits are bicolimits in Cat. Proof. As Cat is a (finitely) combinatorial model category a filtered colimit of equivalences is again an equivalence [7]. The equivalence of (1) and (3) in Proposition 6 gives the result. 4.2. The final decomposition. Our terminology below differs slightly from that used by Rosick´y in 3.2 and 3.3 of [22]. Given a suitable monoidal model category V, such as our Cat or SSet, and a weight W ∈ [J, V] with cofibrant replacement qc : Wc → W in the projective model structure, he calls W homotopy invariant if for each objectwise cofibrant diagram D : Jop → V the induced morphism qc ⋆ D : Wc ⋆ D → W ⋆ D is a weak equivalence in V. In Cat the cofibrant replacement of a weight W is the map qW : QW → W considered throughout whilst every object in Cat is cofibrant; it now follows from Proposition 6 that a weight W : J → Cat is homotopy invariant in Rosick´y’s sense just when W-colimits are bicolimits in Cat. For the final decomposition we need a notion of closure which quantifies over diagrams as well as weights. Consider a full subcategory : A → B and a class Φ of pairs of weights and diagrams Φ = {(Wi : Ji → Cat, Di : Jop i → B); i ∈ I} with each colimit Wi ⋆ Di existing in B. By the 1-step closure of A in B under colimits of type Φ we mean the full subcategory of B consisting of A together with each colimit of the form Wi ⋆ Di for (Wi, Di) ∈ Φ where Di is a diagram taking values in A. In a similar manner the 2-step closure is obtained by adding Φ-colimits with diagrams taking values in the 1-step closure, and so on.3 Theorem 8. Each flexible weight of [J, Cat] lies in the (4-step) closure of the finite coproducts of representables in [J, Cat] under colimits of type Φ, where a pair (W : K → Cat, D : Kop → [J, Cat]) belongs to Φ just when (1) W is a sifted weight. (2) W-colimits are bicolimits in Cat. (3) Each diagram D takes values amongst flexible weights and each colimit W ⋆D is flexible. Proof. Arbitrary coproducts of representables are flexible by 2.4. In any category, or 2-category, an arbitrary coproduct can be constructed using filtered colimits 3The limit of this process is the closure discussed in 3.5 of [11]. 14 JOHN BOURKE of finite coproducts—in particular each coproduct of representables can be constructed as a filtered colimit of finite coproducts of representables in [J, Cat]. Filtered colimits certainly commute with finite products in Cat, and so are sifted, and are bicolimits by Corollary 7; thus arbitary coproducts lie in the 1-step closure. We saw in Theorem 5 that any flexible weight can be constructed from coproducts of representables in three stages by taking sifted flexible colimits, always of flexible weights. As discussed in 4.1 flexible colimits are bicolimits in Cat—thus each flexible weight lies in the 4-step closure. References [1] Albert, M. H., and Kelly, G. M. The closure of a class of colimits. Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 51, 1-2 (1988), 1–17. [2] Badzioch, B. Algebraic theories in homotopy theory. Annals of Mathematics 155, 3 (2002), 895–913. [3] Bergner, J. E. Rigidification of algebras over multi-sorted theories. Alg. Geom. Topology 6 (2005), 1925–1955. [4] Bird, G. J., Kelly, G. M., Power, A. J., and Street, R. Flexible limits for 2-categories. Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 61, 1 (1989), 1–27. [5] Blackwell, R., Kelly, G. M., and Power, A. J. Two-dimensional monad theory. Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 59, 1 (1989), 1–41. [6] Bourke, J., and Garner, R. On semiflexible, flexible and pie algebras. Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra (In press). [7] Dugger, D. Combinatorial model categories have presentations. Advances in Mathematics 164, 1 (2001), 177–201. [8] Gambino, N. Homotopy limits for 2-categories. Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 145, 1 (2008), 43–63. [9] Hovey, M. Model categories, vol. 63 of Mathematical Surveys and Monographs. American Mathematical Society, 1999. [10] Kelly, G. M. Doctrinal adjunction. In Category Seminar (Sydney, 1972/1973), vol. 420 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer, 1974, pp. 257–280. [11] Kelly, G. M. Basic concepts of enriched category theory, vol. 64 of London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series. Cambridge University Press, 1982. [12] Kelly, G. M. Elementary observations on 2-categorical limits. Bulletin of the Australian Mathematical Society 39, 2 (1989), 301–317. [13] Kelly, G. M., Lack, S., and Walters, R. F. C. Coinverters and categories of fractions for categories with structure. Appl. Categ. Structures 1, 1 (1993), 95–102. [14] Kelly, G. M., and Schmitt, V. Notes on enriched categories with colimits of some class. Theory and Applications of Categories 14 (2005), 399–423. [15] Lack, S. Codescent objects and coherence. Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 175, 1-3 (2002), 223–241. [16] Lack, S. Homotopy-theoretic aspects of 2-monads. Journal of Homotopy and Related Structures 7, 2 (2007), 229–260. [17] Lack, S. A 2-categories companion. In Towards higher categories, vol. 152 of IMA Vol. Math. Appl. Springer, 2010, pp. 105–191. [18] Lack, S., and Shulman, M. Enhanced 2-categories and limits for lax morphisms. Advances in Mathematics 229, 1 (2011), 294–356. [19] Makkai, M., and Par´e, R. Accessible categories: the foundations of categorical model theory, vol. 104 of Contemporary Mathematics. American Mathematical Society, 1989. [20] Power, J., and Robinson, E. A characterization of pie limits. Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 110, 1 (1991), 33–47. [21] Riehl, E. Algebraic model structures. New York Journal of Mathematics 17 (2011), 17 (2011) 173–231 173–231. A COLIMIT DECOMPOSITION FOR HOMOTOPY ALGEBRAS IN CAT 15 [22] Rosick´y, J. Rigidification of algebras over essentially algebraic theories. Preprint, arXiv:1206.0422v1 (2012). [23] Street, R. Categorical and combinatorial aspects of descent theory. Appl. Categ. Structures 12, 5-6 (2004), 537–576. Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Masaryk University, Kotl´aˇrsk´a 2, Brno 60000, Czech Republic E-mail address: bourkej@math.muni.cz